OTHER BOOKS BY DR. W. S. URQUHART THE HISTORICAL AND THE ETERNAL CHRIST 9 ‘ I have not read anything sounder or more impressive on the subject.’ The late Principal Denny. THE UPANISHADS AND LIFE ‘ Dr. Urquhart is not a whit behind the best of the German students of Hindu philosophy. ... He is scrupulously fair to the Hindu faith and the Hindu philosophy. . . . There is a whole life’s study in the book.’ Expository Times. PANTHEISM AND THE VALUE OF LIFE, with special reference to Indian Philosophy. ‘ The seven hundred pages may well rank with the best that have been written upon Hindu thought. . . . They are at once destructive, constructive and impartial. There is no connected problem which is not freely and fully dis¬ cussed to our greater enlightenment.’ Times Literary Supplement . ‘ The author has thoroughly mastered the literature of the subject and has brought to bear upon the subject a critical acumen of a high order. Indian readers who may not be able to agree with him in all that he says will nevertheless give him credit for an effort to be just and impartial.’ Hindustan Review. ‘ The volume is a masterpiece both in its investigation and its criticism of Indian philosophy.’ London Quarterly Review. THEOSOPHY AND CHRISTIAN THOUGHT ‘ Dr. Urquhart’s object, which he carries out in moderate compass in a lucid and instructive way, is to expound in popular fashion the main doctrines of Theosophy, its antecedents, origin and growth ; and to combine with critic^m a real appreciation of the help it can give to the understanding and practical application of Christianity.’ Times Literary Supplement. * Dr. Urquhart has already won his spurs in the fields of philosophic thought by a remarkable study of Pantheism. And this book is .mSHsed by the same qualities of insight, scholarship, logical penetration and lucidity of expression.’ British Weekly. ‘ A masterly exposition of the main doctrines of theosophy, its relation to science and philosophy, and its religious and ethical value.’ Expository Times , f?4> H- ft THE RELIGIOUS QUEST OF INDIA®’®’® EDITED BY J. N. FARQUHAR, M.A. D.Litt. (Oxon.), Hon. D.D. (Aberdeen) PROFESSOR OF COMPARATIVE RELIGION MANCHESTER UNIVERSITY H. D. GRISWOLD, M.A., PhJD, D.D. FORMERLY SECRETARY OF THE COUNCIL OF THE AMERICAN PRESBYTERIAN MISSION IN INDIA AND E. C. DEWICK, M.A. (Cantab.) LITERARY SECRETARY, NATIONAL COUNCIL OF YOUNG MEN’S CHRISTIAN ASSOCIATIONS INDIA AND CEYLON 8 Aoc. No. UNIFORM WITH THIS VOLUME Already Published INDIAN THEISM THE HEART OF JAINISM THE TREASURE OF THE MAGI. REDEMPTION : HINDU AND CHRISTIAN. THE RELIGIOUS LITERATURE OF INDIA. THE RITES OF THE TWICE-BORN. HINDU ETHICS THE RELIGION OF THE RIGVEDA. By Nicol Macnicol, M.A., D.Litt. Pp. xvi + 292. Price 6s. net. By Mrs. Sinclair Stevenson, M.A., Sc.D. (Dublin). Pp. xxiv-l-336. Price 7s. 6d. By James Moulton, D.Litt., D.D., D.C.L. Pp.xv 4-273. Price 8s. 6d. By Sydney Cave, D.D. (Lond.). Pp. xii + 263. Price xos. 6d. By J. N. Farquhar, M.A., D.Litt. (Oxon.), Hon. D.D. (Aberdeen). Pp. xxviii + 451. Price 18s. By Mrs. Sinclair Stevenson, M.A., Sc.D. (Dublin). Pp. xxiv-f 474. Price 21s. By John McKenzie, M.A. Pp. xii 4-267. Price 10s. 6d. By H. D. Qriswold, Ph.D. D.D. Pp. xxiv-f-392. Price 12s. 6d. In Preparation ISLAM IN INDIA . . By M. T. Titus, D.Phil (Moradabad). EDITORIAL PREFACE . mi$M npHE writers of this series of volumes on the variant forms ox religious life in India are governed in their work by two impelling motives. 1. They endeavour to work in the sincere and sympathetic spirit of science. They desire to understand the perplexingly involved developments of thought and life in India and dis¬ passionately to estimate their value. They recognize the futility of any such attempt to understand and evaluate, unless it is grounded in a thorough historical study of the phenomena in¬ vestigated. In recognizing the fact they do no more than share what is common ground among all modern students of religion of any repute. But they also believe that it is necessary to set the practical side of each system in living relation to the beliefs and the literature and that, in this regard, the close and direct contact which they have each had with Indian religious life ought to prove a source of valuable light. For, until a clear understanding has been gained of the practical influence exerted, by the habits of worship, by the practice of the ascetic, devo¬ tional, or occult discipline, by the social organization and by the family system, the real impact of the faith upon the life of the individual and the community cannot be estimated: and, without the advantage of extended personal intercourse, a trustworthy account of the religious experience of a community can scarcely be achieved by even the most careful student. 2 . They seek*to set each form of Indian religion by the side of Christianity in such a way that the relationship may stand out clear. Jesus Christ has become to them the light of all their seeing and they believe Him destined to be the light of the world. They are persuaded that sooner or later the age-long quest of the Indian spirit for religious truth and power will find in Him at once its goal and a new starting-point, and they will be content if the preparation of this series contributes in the vi EDITORIAL PREFACE smallest degree to hasten this consummation. If there be readers to whom this motive is unwelcome, they may be reminded that no man approaches the study of a religion without religious convictions, either positive or negative: for both reader and writer, therefore, it is better that these should be explicitly stated at the outset. Moreover, even a complete lack of sym¬ pathy with the motive here acknowledged need not diminish a reader’s interest in following an honest and careful attempt to "bring the religions of India into comparison with the religion which to-day is their only possible rival, and to which they largely owe their present noticeable and significant revival. It is possible that to some minds there may seem to be a measure of incompatibility between these two motives. The writers, however, feel otherwise. For them the second motive reinforces the first: for they have found that he who would lead others into a new faith must first of all understand the faith that is theirs already—understand it, moreover, sympathetically, with a mind quick to note not its weaknesses alone but that in it which has enabled it to survive and has given it its power over the hearts of those who profess it. The duty of the Editors of the series is limited to seeing that the volumes are in general harmony with the principles here described. Each writer is alone responsible for the opinions expressed in his volume, whether in regard to Indian religions or to Christianity. THE RELIGIOUS QUEST OF INDIA THE VEDANTA AND MODERN THOUGHT BY W. S. URQUHART, M.A., D.Litt. PRINCIPAL OF THE SCOTTISH CHURCHES COLLEGE CALCUTTA AND PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY; FELLOW OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALCUTTA ; PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF CALCUTTA Author of The Historical and the Eternal Christ; The Upanishads and Life ; 'Pantheism and the Value of Life ; Theosophy and Christian Thought ,* &c. HUMPHREY MILFORD , OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS LONDON EDINBURGH GLASGOW NEW YORK TORONTO MELBOURNE CAPETOWN BOMBAY I928 PRINTED IN ENGLAND AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS, OXFORD BY JOHN JOHNSON, PRINTER TO THE UNIVERSITY TO Professor W. L. DAVIDSON, LL.D. EMERITUS PROFESSOR OF LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS IN THE UNIVERSITY OF ABERDEEN AND Professor W. R. SORLEY, LL.D. FORMERLY PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF ABERDEEN, AND NOW KNIGHT- BRIDGE PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE MY TEACHERS IN PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF ABERDEEN Vw A *' AUTHOR’S PREFACE I N the ever-increasing mass of literature which has been de¬ voted to the criticism and appreciation of Indian thought, a tendency to extremes has constantly manifested itself. On the one hand we find amongst outside critics signs of a disposition . to undervalue the results of Indian speculation. Over-zealous attempts are sometimes made to derive from alien sources the most important elements in Oriental philosophy, and when such attempts are shown by serious scholars to be almost alto¬ gether impossible, recourse is taken to a superior and slightly patronizing attitude in which, no doubt, expressions of depre¬ ciation are politely avoided, but the place of genuine and sym¬ pathetic appreciation is occupied by intermittent ejaculations of wonder as to how a people who have not had the benefits of the cultural inheritance which the superior critics themselves enjoy, should have been capable of so much as has actually been accomplished in India. Needless to say, the feeling which is aroused by an attitude of this kind amongst those upon whom judgement is thus summarily passed, is one of irritation rather than of gratitude. The other extreme is undiscriminating admiration. Under the influence of this mood, writers, both in the East and in the West, vie with each other in asseverating that everything that is good comes from the East, and that nothing is good which does not come from the East. It is only by Eastern windows that ‘when daylight comes, comes in the light*. Moved by a spurious kind of cosmopolitanism or by an almost childish desire to vindicate their own broadmindedness, certain Western philo¬ sophers of the type here indicated have gone the length of declaring that the Orient has a monopoly of spirituality, that the West is blatantly materialistic, and that all the more important elements in early European philosophy may be traced to the Eastern influences which moulded the precursors of Plato, or to x ii PREFACE the currents of philosophic thought which moved from East to West in the centuries immediately preceding or immediately suc¬ ceeding the commencement of the Christian era. Three-quarters of a century ago Cousin described the East as The native land of the highest philosophy’, and Schopenhauer earlier gave utter¬ ance to the unrestrained generalization that ‘in the whole world there is no study so beneficial and elevating as that of the Upanishads’. Writers of a later date have to an even greater extent allowed their enthusiasm to overwhelm the undoubted elements of truth which are contained in such assertions. Opinions of this sort have, of course, been eagerly welcomed by some Indian writers, who have perhaps a keener relish for the compliment which appeals to patriotism than for the valua¬ tion which depends upon a balanced judgement. We come across, e.g., such statements as the followingj ‘India has given to humanity the main outlines at least of the whole of the philo¬ sophy and religion of the world !’' 1 Although, however, such sweeping statements are by no means isolated, it would be al¬ together unfair to suggest that judgements of this kind are passed without qualification by the generality of Indian writers on philosophy. A more temperate and tenable position is taken up, e.g., by Prof. S. N. Das Gupta, who claims only that,‘most of the prob¬ lems still debated in modern philosophical thought occurred in more or less divergent form to the philosophers of India ’. 2 It cannot certainly be contended that in the course of the world’s history India has been responsible for the only philosophical thought worthy of the name, but it may be argued with a con¬ siderable amount of justification that, at a very early period in intellectual development, the greater philosophical problems had presented themselves to the Indian consciousness and had re¬ ceived penetrating and illuminating treatment. India has had, 1 Prof. Drivedi, Introduction to the Mandukya U. II. s Das Gupta, p. viii. PREFACE xiii and still has, a most important contribution to make to the thought of the world, and is well qualified to make this contribu¬ tion by the intensity with which throughout the centuries she has devoted herself to her philosophical and philosophico- religious task. Rarely has metaphysical speculation afforded to any people so absorbing an interest. As Prof. Radhakrishnan says: 4 In many other countries reflection on the nature of exis¬ tence is a luxury of life. The serious moments are given to action, while the pursuit of philosophy comes up as a paren¬ thesis. In ancient India philosophy was not an auxiliary to any other science or art, but always held a prominent position of independence.’ A study of the Vedanta leads to many general reflections on the relations between philosophy and religion, and in particular to the questions how far such a philosophy can satisfy religious needs and how far it can be regarded as a preparation for Christianity. I have tried to set forth some conclusions as to these and allied problems. Sankara has been taken as the typical philosopher of the school, for reasons which appear to me to be satisfactory; and the general trend of opinion amongst Indian writers and thinkers themselves would appear to justify this concentration. It has been my endeavour to carry out my task in a spirit of fairness, and to avoid the mistake of merely work¬ ing^ towards a foregone conclusion. And I have no hesitation in saying that such studies as I have been able to make in Indian philosophy have confirmed me in the faith that God has not left Himself without a witness in the characteristic thought of India, that much of it is unconsciously anticipative of Christian thought, and that Jesus Christ will one day be recognized there also as the ‘light which lighteth every man that cometh into the world’. Amongst the many books which have been consulted, I have 1 Radhakrishnan, I. 22. xiv PREFACE found the first volume of Prof. Radhakrishnan’s Indian Philo¬ sophy, the first volume of Prof. S. N. Das Gupta’s History of Indian Philosophy, and Dr. J. N. Farquhar’s Outline of the Religious Literature of India specially useful as works of re¬ ference. Dr. Farquhar, also, and the Rev. E. C. Dewick have given me much help in the preparation of my manuscript for the press. I should like to express finally my great indebtedness to my wife for many useful suggestions and for much assistance in reading both manuscript and proofs. W. S. URQUHART. Scottish Churches College, Calcutta, 1928. CONTENTS I. Introductory. The Affiliations and the Importance of the Vedanta. Vedantic Ideas in the Vedas 11. Anticipations of Vedantic Ideas in the Upanishads. The Vedanta Sutras. The Gita. The Karikas of Gaudapada ....... III. Sankara and Ramanuja: Their Lives, their Com¬ mentaries, and their Traditional Philosophical Significance ....... IV. The Approach to Sankara’s Central Teaching. Preliminary Conditions. His Conception of Au¬ thority. The Idealistic Attitude. His Relation to Buddhism ....... V. The Ultimate Unity. The Two Orders of Know¬ ledge. The Place of Works VI. The Doctrines of Maya and Avidya. Relation to Kant. The God of Qualities . ... VII. The Destiny of the Individual Soul. The Place of • Ethics in the Vedanta ..... VIII. Some Comparisons between the Vedanta and Modern Philosophical Thought IX. The Religious Value of the Vedanta, and Some Conclusions . . . Index . • 25! ABBREVIATIONS Aiyar: C. N. Krishnaswami Aiyar, Life and Times of Sankara* Carpenter: Dr. J. Estlin Carpenter, Theism in Medieval India. Das Gupta: Prof. S. N. Das Gupta, A History of Indian Philosophy. Deussen, S. V.: Deussen, System of the Vedanta , Chicago, 1912. Deussen, P. U.: Deussen, Philosophy of the Upanishads. Farquhar: Dr. J. N. Farquhar, Outline of the Religious Literature of India. Goreh: Nehemiah Goreh, Mirror of Hindu Philosophical Systems. Griswold: Dr* H. D. Griswold, The Religion of the Rigveda. Happel: Happel, Grundanschauungen der Inder. J. R. A. S.: Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society. Kirtikar: Vasudeva J. Kirtikar, Studies in Vedanta. Muller, S. S.: Max Muller, Six Systems of Indian Philosophy. Pal: D..N. Pal, Sankara the Sublime. Pringle-Pattison: Prof. Pringle-Pattison, The Idea of God. Radhakrishnan: Prof. S. Radhakrishnan, Indian Philosophy. Schopenhauer: Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Idea (trans. by Haldane and Kemp). S. B.E.: Sacred Books of the East. S. B. Hr. Sacred Books of the Hindus. Sen: Mr. P. N, Sen, Philosophy of the Vedanta. Shastri, B. K.: Prof. B. K. Shastri, The Bhakti Cult in Ancient India. Shastri, K.: Prof. Kokileswar Shastri, The Advaita Philosophy. Shastri, P. D.: Prof. P. D. Shastri, The Doctrine of Mayd. U.: Upanishads. INTRODUCTORY. THE AFFILIATIONS AND IMPORTANCE OF THE VEDANTA. VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDAS' A COMP ARISON between Eastern and Western philosophy should aim at proving, not that one is superior to the other, but rather that the one may be supplemented or corrected by the other. When the prevailing points of view are different and origins and methods so diverse, it is to be expected that the resulting philosophies will present strikingly contrasted virtues and limitations, and that fullness of truth can be reached only through co-operation. Max Muller, e.g., was acutely conscious of the narrowness of conception which might arise from an exclusive nurture on the thought of the Jews, the Greeks, or the Romans, and felt that from India especially we might derive ‘that correction which is wanted in order to make our inner life more perfect, more comprehensive, more universal, in fact, more truly human’. 1 Thus, in seeking for that unity which is behind all the diversity of the history of thought, we must not be too anxious to discover unity at the expense of diversity. Such haste has led to many futile efforts to establish affiliations and derivations which are hardly warranted by the facts. Simi¬ larities indeed there are, fundamental and impressive, but the differences must also be clearly kept in view, if the fullness of the co-operative work of the human spirit is to be realized; and these differences, as Emerson reminds us, 2 are no more sur¬ prising than the variety of the acts of one man in which we recognize the same character. The broad and deep similarities between Greek and Indian thinkers have frequently been noted, so that there is not much risk of our forgetting them. Many recent writers have found an almost complete accord, e.g. between the Vedanta and the abstract philosophy of the Greek Eleatics. For Parmenides, amongst the latter, the only reality is the one and indivisible Being, destitute of qualities and superior to all distinctions of place and changes in time. And did not Plato, equally with his - India, What Can It Teach Us?, 6. 3 Essay on History. 2 AFFILIATIONS AND IMPORTANCE Eastern fellow searchers after truth, seek for an eternal beyond change and an essential reality behind appearances—a universal Being in which all particularity is merged? Yet even in regard to that ultimate reality which was the common object of search, there are important differences between Indian and Greek con¬ ceptions. The Hindu philosopher seemed from the first to rebel against the thought of limits, whereas for the Greek, except at a very early stage, the unlimited seemed to be metaphysically undesirable. He sought above all for clarity and precision of conception, whilst to the Indian mind the one which was the goal of his endeavour was attractive just because of its vague¬ ness, and because it could not properly be described either as Being or non-Being. The Indian thinker could not intellectualize this Being, and did not wish to do so, but only to grasp it by in¬ tuition, under an overpowering sense of that mysterium tremen - dum which a recent writer has emphasized as the essence of the religious consciousness . 1 The Being of the Vedanta has indeed many points of similarity to the Being of Plato, but the latter does not emphasize so earnestly, or rest so contentedly in, a transcendent reality, and it is with a certain amount of reluc¬ tance that he falls back on the aid of those myths through which alone he feels that he can hint at its character. Thus, when he relies on philosophy alone, the Being of Plato tends to become more fully intellectualized than the Being of the Vedanta. Plato obtains a logical, if not an actual, transition from the One to the Many, whereas the Eastern philosopher is content with a vaguer fundamental unity from which there cannot be a logical transition to the multiplicity of the world, and in con¬ trast to whose impenetrable vastness the particularity of ordinary experience is best explained by being left unexplained. In fact it is even doubtful whether in an Indian connexion we are justi¬ fied in making use of the phrase mysterium tremendum ; for this might be taken to suggest a Reality which might some day be explained, whereas the Indian thinker was rather inclined to the idea of a reality which he neither hoped nor desired to explain. It can, perhaps, be said with truth that it is in the philosophy of religion that India has made her greatest contribution to the 1 Cf, Otto , Das Heilige, passim. OF THE VEDANTA 3 thought of the world. Nowhere is it altogether possible to draw a hard-and-fast line between the philosophy of religion and philosophy in general, but this distinction is least of all admis- sible in India, where it might be said that the conditions and intensity of the search for a solution of life’s problems and the ,character of the solutions offered alike invite to a religious attitude. The almost despairing realization of the need for deliverance, together with the indefiniteness of the Reality which is conceived to be the only refuge, predisposes the searcher to a mystical mood and makes it impossible for him to be content with coldly intellectual satisfaction. The very grading of our experiences in such a way as to place deep sleep above the dreaming consciousness, and this again above the waking consciousness, in itself indicates a disposition towards mystic and abstract unity. The Indian mind is, like Newman’s, subtle in analysis, but it is also simple in belief, capable of a concentration of the whole being upon an ideal of unity with a degree of intensity which is rarely equalled elsewhere, and which is of itself sufficient to carry the human spirit across the border-line—if there be a border-line—between philosophy and religion. As Prof. Das Gupta says, ‘The systems of philo¬ sophy in India were not stirred up merely by the speculative demands of the human mind, but by a deep craving after the realization of the religious purpose of life .’ 1 And the more intense statement of Deussen is also justified* ‘No people on earth took religion so seriously, none toiled on the way to salva¬ tion as they did. Their reward for this was to have got, if not the most scientific, yet the most inward and immediate expres¬ sion of the deepest secret of being.’ 3 j The Hindu regarded one-pointedness (ekagrata) as the indis¬ pensable condition of intellectual penetration into the deep mysteries of the universe; and, although this qualification may be difficult for outsiders to appreciate, and the application of it may lead to certain extravagances and peculiarities, it undoubt¬ edly illustrates the facility with which the philosophy of India connects itself inextricably with religion. Its use is allied with an inclination and aptitude for a quiet and contemplative life, and with a preference for the intuitive to the discursive in 1 Das Gupta, I. 71. * Deussen, S. V., 49. 4 AFFILIATIONS AND IMPORTANCE method and for intensity to extensity in the resulting knowledge. It favours passivity more than activity, and indicates a belief in the service to thought which may be rendered by the quiet in land ^ We may say that, under the conditions described, the pre¬ vailing tendency of thought is in the direction of a pantheism of an idealistic character. India has been described as ‘radically pantheistic and that from its cradle onwards’; and its pantheism has been more continuous than in any other country. This means a readiness to find close at hand the materials for both philosophical speculation andreligious devotion,andstrengthens the alliance between the satisfactions of the mind and of the spirit. Every bush may be afire with God and every natural event a manifestation of His indwelling, and, subjectively, religious devotion and speculative insight are through pan¬ theism brought very close together. Further, the alliance between philosophy and religion is also favoured by the contemplative passivity which we have noted as a characteristic of the Indian attitude. From this arises a certain conservativeness, and a readiness to look to the. past rather than to the future, expressing itself often in a belief in a golden age set far back in a period of remote antiquity. This again connects itself with a reverence for the authority of tradition and an intense appreciation of the value of even the smallest details of the sacred lore. This reverence attaches itself frequently to ritualistic formulae. Take, e.g., the impor¬ tance assigned to the syllable Om (or Aim). We have here not a meaningless catchword or charm, but a symbol indicative of a whole philosophical position. It is analysed and re-analysed to the fullest possible extent, and everything of possible value is extracted from it. It is used.alike as a guide to concentration and as the herald of a prophetic vision of the highest truth. Similarly, but in a broader way, the reverence for tradition, religiously valued, is seen in the constant endeavour to relate philosophical conclusions to the pronouncements of the earliest literature; and the consequence of this is to linkup speculation with that period in the world’s history when religion and philosophy had hardly begun to differentiate themselves from each other. VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA 5 Thus there are many reasons which would lead us to look for both a religious origin and a religious design for philosophy in India; and when we turn more particularly to the philosophy of the Vedanta we find that our expectations are fully justified. The very term Vedanta is an illustration of the tendencies we have just been indicating. There are many possible mean¬ ings, as we shall see, but even if we take account of only the primary and almost mechanically literal meaning—‘the end of the Veda’—there is here suggested a desire to connect the speculative ideas with the body of religious literature which has the greatest claim to antiquity, and therefore the greatest authority. But this also involves the linking up of the ideas with the popular religion which the literature enshrines. The etymo¬ logy itself indicates that at the end of the process of satisfying the requirements of ritual, at the end of the explanation of the significance of the ceremonies, then might come the deeper speculations. Thus, from the first, speculation could be secured against the charge of being merely academic, and the founda¬ tions at least were laid for the Indian conception of the closest possible union between religion and philosophy. In a com¬ parison between Hinduism and Buddhism Dr. J. Estlin Car¬ penter says with truth: ‘The forces of Hinduism were rooted in a remoter past, they were intertwined more closely (than those of Buddhism) even with the localities as well as with the habits of the popular religion, they sprang more directly out of the common heart, they appealed more directly to the common mind. 51 This generalization may be applied to later develop¬ ments as well as to earliest origins. In the Mahabhdrata, XII. 55, the term ‘Vedanta’ is taken to denote the Upanishads, and this may be regarded as its primary reference. It expresses the essential ideas of the Upanishads, and, through the Aranyakas and the Brahmanas, reaches back to the very oldest extant religious literature of India, viz. the Vedas. For the Upanishads were the concluding part of the Aranyakas, and contained the essential doctrines in which the theosophical interpretations contained in the latter might be regarded as finding their culmination. The Aranyakas, again, were the hand-books—to speak metaphorically—and contained 1 Carpenter, 117. 6 VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA the most useful parts, or the most valuable interpretations, of the Brahmanas. They were ‘Brahmanas appointed for the vow of an anchorite’, and through them the Vanaprastha, or ‘dweller in the woods , might be assisted in pieparation foi his hermit life. Their background was formed by the Brahmanas, which were ritual text-books belonging to a later and less original age than that of the Vedas, embodying sacerdotal tradition, and elaborating the ideas of the Vedas into a complex, cumbrous, and ever-growing ceremonial. Finally, passing still farther up the stream of time, we come to the Vedas, comprising in the Rigveda the ancient and beautiful hymns to the gods which are amongst the most cherished possessions of Indian literature, and showing affinities with that body of ideas which is common to Indo-European thought in general and perhaps to primitive thought throughout the world. Yet, while we use the word ‘primitive’, we must be careful in connexion with the Rigveda not to allow it to convey any hint of disparagement, for these hymns present to us exceedingly wonderful intuitions of the Divine, all the more impressive because they are so near to the beginnings of the religious thought of the world. The Vedas comprise also the Samaveda, a book of chants to be sung by the priests at the time of the Soma worship; and the Yajurveda, which contains formulae, partly in prose and partly in verse, designed for use at the various sacrifices. To these must also be added the Atharvaveda, later and less important than the other Vedas and considerably different from them in thought and feeling, inasmuch as, it shows traces of magical and superstitious ideas which had crept in from a lower stratum of thought, and were perhaps both cause and effect of a growingly pessimistic mood. Thus by an unbroken chain the Upanishads are connected in a backward direction with the Vedas; but as the truth contained in the Vedas is considered to be inexhaustible, we must also look forwards, and regard as a continuation of the chain every effort towards putting this truth in a more serviceable form or towards giving a fuller interpretation of it. Therefore the Vedanta will comprise not only the Upanishads and their prede¬ cessors, but also their successors. The Upanishads are later summarized in the Vedanta Sutras, a collection of aphorisms in VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA 7 which the salient points of the Upanishads are emphasized. They are of the nature of succinct summaries for memorizing, serving the purpose of notes for discussions continued from century to century in the different schools. While these sum¬ maries might have been intelligible to those who had taken part in, or were familiar with, the discussions based upon them, they could not but be somewhat obscure to others not so privileged. Thus they were practically useless without the commentaries which followed at a later date. In one sense, therefore, the culmination of the Vedanta is to be found in commentaries such as those of Sankara, who flourished about the ninth century, and Ramanuja of the twelfth century, and many others, whose activities, of very varying degrees of importance, extended as far down as the seventeenth century. To this whole development the name Vedanta is, as a rule, given, but variations in the application of the term should not be left unnoticed. As we have seen 1 the primary application of the term is to the Upanishads, but in the view of Prof. S. N. Das Gupta, the Sutras 'form the original authoritative work of the Vedanta’? To these and the Upanishads, the Gita is added as a third authoritative source-book of the Vedanta philosophy. Further, when the age of the commentators arrives, there is a natural tendency to claim exclusive importance for one or other of them. Usually Sankara obtains the pre-eminence. Mr. P. N. Sen, e.g., says: 'The philosophy of Sankara has now been unalterably identified with the Vedanta philosophy; it is the Vedanta par excellence" 3 Ramanuja, of course, has also his votaries, though not perhaps to the same extent. The question of the importance of the various periods and contributors relatively to each other will come up for later discussion. Tn the meantime it is sufficient to notice that the name is not im¬ properly applied to the whole course of the development. On the whole it would seem that the most common average usage throughout India is to allow this wider reference to the whole development, but at the same time to assign to the philosophy of Sankara the central place in the field of the Vedantic consciousness, and this will be, for the most part, the practice followed in this book. 1 Supra , p. 5. 2 Das Gupta, I. 3 Philosophy of the Vedanta, 6. 8 YEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA We have found that the literal meaning of Vedanta is ‘end of the Veda’, but allied meanings are ‘dogma of the Veda’, ‘final aim of the Veda 5 , &c. It does not seem necessary to decide between the claims of these various meanings, because the later may be seen to arise out of the primary by an entirely natural development of thought. The primary meaning would direct attention especially to the Upanishads, the philosophical specu¬ lations which come at the end of the ritual formulae and direc¬ tions found in the Brahmanas, or, more exactly, as a subsequent stage of the concentrated form in which these formulae appear in the Aranyakas. But these speculations, when the thought of their temporal sequence is transcended, might very well be taken as the essence of essence, the central doctrine, to express which—or to call forth the expression of which—was the aim or final purpose of the Veda. In the case of the individual pupil, also, what he learnt at the end of his course, what the Guru might communicate to him with a considerable air of secrecy and impressiveness in those days immediately preceding separa¬ tion which have special significance for all masters and pupils, would naturally seem to be the most valuable of all the instruc¬ tions given during the years of training and that for which the whole process had simply been an anticipation. To have intro¬ duced at an earlier stage distinctions of value between the various parts of the total body of instruction, distinctions, in other w T ords, selective of certain truths as worthy of being raised to the rank of central dogmas, or even to have made the idea of such distinctions explicit at all, might not have been judicious, inasmuch as it might have led to a neglect on the part of the pupil of the necessary preparatory stages. But there is not the same difficulty if it is supposed that the distinction might have emerged according to the unconscious logic of events by which a situation only gradually yields up its full significance. And the historical process is not altogether different from the process as it goes on in the mind of an indi¬ vidual pupil. People in general are at first interested only in the succession of events and take them as they come; it is only later that their significance emerges and is realized. Thus whatever stands at the end of any process comes gradually to be regarded as containing the essential meaning of the process and as consti- VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA 9 tuting the aim at which the whole process is directed. If, further, at any special period in the development this essential meaning is strikingly, even if unsystematically, set forth, the resulting situation will be that, during subsequent periods, the further interpretation of the central meaning will be the pre¬ dominant concern of thinkers. Thus, by considering the matter along these lines, we can easily understand that the term Ved anta will cease to invite attention most of all to its temporal aspect and will come to indicate rather a purposeful and sustained endeavour to penetrate to the very depths of the mysteries alluded to in the earliest sacred books and to set forth the results of investigation in doctrinal statements possessing ever-increas¬ ing clearness, consistency, and comprehensiveness. In the Vedanta, as well as in other Indian philosophies, we may notice a remarkable unity of development more closely knit than in Western philosophy. In connexion with the latter a conspicuous philosopher generally adopts the plan of enuncia¬ ting a fairly complete system of thought. This may to a certain extent be elaborated by his immediate successors, but before very long the system as a whole is superseded by another system which may, indeed, grow out of its predecessor, but regards it rather as affording material for criticism than as possessing con¬ tinuing authority. For the Western philosopher it is true that our little systems have their day and cease to be. On account of the fundamental similarities of human nature there will, of course, be repetitions of the old in the new, but such repetitions are not deliberate and in any case tend to be discouraged. In India the case is very different. Throughout the centuries a school of philosophy continues to be dominated by certain leading ideas, and free development, though it is not absent, is of comparatively subordinate importance. The Sutra form of literature lent itself especially to this kind of combination of old and new according to which the old unmistakably controlled, although it did not entirely exclude, the new. As has been already indicated, the Sutras were summaries for memory or notes for discussion, fully intelligible only to those who had taken part in the discussion. Inasmuch as they were only notes, a certain amount of freedom of treatment and therefore variation was possible, but the main lines of thought were dominatingly 10 VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA fixed by the Sutras and by the more authoritative of the ancient teachers. 1 The newer teachers would not feel at liberty to depart from the Sutras or to contradict the older teachers in regard to any important issue. Reinterpretation alone was pos¬ sible, with the limited object of adjusting the traditional doc¬ trines to opposing tendencies which had emerged at later dates or of introducing topics on which the earlier teachers had kept silence. It was of fundamental importance that authority should be maintained and tradition respected, and thus the philosophical task consisted to a large extent in the repetition and elaboration of earlier views. Thus the unity of Eastern philosophy as compared with Western might be illustrated by the poetical unity of alliteration as contrasted with the less obvious but more organic unity of blank verse. Or, perhaps, in temporary disregard of the fact that it is maintained through centuries, the Indian unity might be compared to that of a single individual as he grows from infancy to manhood, in contrast with the unity of successive generations of men within a single system of national or racial development. Prof. S. N. Das Gupta points out with justice that ‘it is not possible to write any history of successive z philo¬ sophies of India, but it is necessary that each system should be studied and interpreted in all the growth it has acquired through the successive ages of history from its conflicts with the rival systems. . . / Earlier in the same paragraph, and perhaps with special reference to the Vedanta, he says: ‘A system in the Sutras is weak and helpless as a new-born babe, but if we take it along with its developments down to the beginning of^the seventeenth century, it appears as a fully developed man, strong and harmonious in all its limbs. ? 3 It may easily, we think, be maintained that the Vedanta is the most important and most widely influential amongst Indian philosophies. Its 'boldness, depth, and subtlety of speculation,’ 4 have attracted the attention of students everywhere, and it is fundamental in the thought of the simpler people. Other sys¬ tems have arisen in opposition to it, have had temporary success, 1 We may compare this with certain conditions which obtain in Indian music. The rag, which is a fixed form, dominates the structure of any new composition, but, nevertheless, allows considerable freedom for variation. 3 Italics mine. 3 Das Gupta, I. 64. 4 S.B.E* XXXIV, p. xiv. VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA \ ; n and have left their mark upon the body of Vedantic itself. But from the earliest dawn of antiquity to the presfesi^ day the Vedanta has more than held its own. Max Muller claims that it is ‘clearly the native philosophy of India’. 1 It may be claimed to be the first growth of philosophic thought upon the soil of India. Even in the Upanishads traces of other philo¬ sophies are few and far between, and in still earlier literature such indications are practically non-existent, whereas ‘strictly Vedantic concepts meet us at every step in the Hymns, the Brahmanas, the Aranyakas.’ 2 More than sixty years ago Nehemiah Goreh couid speak of other philosophies as having no adherents whilst the Vedanta was ‘held by a large majority of Hindus’. 3 What was true then is still true to-day, provided that we look for signs of its prevalence not only in articulate philosophical expression, but in the more subtle thought and practice-forms which hold an often unacknowledged sway over the community. Having referred briefly to the affiliations and importance of the Vedanta philosophy, we may now turn our attention to a fuller consideration of the emergence of the fundamental ideas in the earliest religious literature. The remainder of this chapter will be taken up mainly with the ideas in the Vedas which seem to be anticipatory of Vedantic doctrine. The Vedas are regarded in India as of fundamental religious importance. According to one Indian writer, a man is an atheist if he disbelieves in the Vedas, but not necessarily so if he disbelieves in God. The dates of the books are variously stated. By strictly orthodox Brahmans they are regarded as eternal, but the word eternal may be modified so as to signify ‘age-long’, and the date of origin retracted only so far as the beginning of the present mundane age, i.e. to over one hundred billion years ago. 4 Even when only calculable periods are considered, there is great diversity of opinion. Tilak and Jacobi favour a very early date, not later than 3500 B.c., basing their conclusions both on astronomical data and on the normally observed slowness of development in India. Other scholars—Max Muller in a former generation and Professors Berriedale Keith and Hopkins at * Mttller, S.S. 115. > lb. 115. 3 Goreh, 217. 4 Cf. Griswold, 67; Das Gupta, 10. 12 VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA the present day—favour dates between 1200 and 800 B.c. It cannot be said that there are sufficient data to enable us to reach a definite conclusion, and the matter can hardly be settled without further archaeological investigation and discovery. In any case we are concerned here not with minute details possibly affected by conclusions as to dates, but with certain broad tendencies which prepare the way for the leading conceptions of the Vedanta. We shall confine our attention chiefly to the Rigveda. The religion of the Veda is for the most part one of light and joyousness, an expression of the trustfulness succeeding to the unreasoning terror of evil spirits which is a frequent accom¬ paniment of animistic religion. The terrors of the darkness have been forgotten as by a child awakening to the light of the morning and to the presence of protecting friends. The be¬ nignant forces of nature are relied upon to triumph over the destructive; and, if occasionally malignant demons should appear, there are assuredly forces in nature of sufficient potency to overcome them and ready to assist those who are careful to worship in the appointed way. The attitude in general is one of simple trustfulness and rather easily satisfied materialism. ‘Lead thou us, O Agni, to increasing riches. 51 £ 0 Usas, waken up for me the sounds of joy, send us the riches of the great/ 2 are amongst the characteristic prayers. The ethical sense cannot be said to be very fully developed. What is upper¬ most in the mind of the worshipper is omission or error in sacrificial ceremony rather than a consciousness of sin. In the hymns addressed to Varuna, indeed, there is much searching of heart and frequent confession of sin, but this deity hardly maintained a place of supremacy in the Vedic pantheon, and in any case the sins confessed are ceremonial rather than moral, sins of ignorance rather than sins of wilfulness, social rather than personal. 3 ‘In whatever way we have sinned against the gods, in whatever manner we have through ignorance neglected thy work, Oh, do not destroy us for these sins 5 and again, ‘O Varuna, deliver us from the sins of our fathers. 5 The gods who are worshipped belong to the three regions of the heavens, the air, and the earth. In Dyaus, the earliest of the Rigveda, I. 13. 3 Ib.48.1. 3 Cf. ib. VII. 89. 5. VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA 13 gods, there is indicated a slight personification of the sky, and this is carried farther in relation to the other gods of the same region, e.g. Varuna, the source of steadfastness, all-seeing, following the flight of ‘the birds that fly through the heaven’, ‘sovran of the sea, and knowing the ships that are thereon To Usas, the radiant goddess of the dawn, as she awakens the joy of the morning and puts to flight the terrors of darkness, many hymns of great beauty are addressed. Visnu also appears in this group of gods, but holds a comparatively subordinate place amongst the Vedic gods generally. Amongst the gods of the atmosphere, or middle region, Indra, almost entirely beneficent in his activities although later to become the god of war, and Rudra, the terrible one, the god of the thunderbolt, are the most important, and they are surrounded by a crowd of minor deities, such as the Maruts, or storm-gods, Vata, the god of the wind, and Parjanya, the god of the rain-cloud. The chief deities of the earth are Agni, Soma, and Yama. Agni is the god of the sacrificial fire, and is described as the youngest of the gods, because he is born anew whenever the sacrificial fire is lit. He is perhaps not strictly an earth-god, as he has also easily intelligible affinities with the air and the sky and with their typical deities, Indra and Surya. The magical and medicinal qualities of the soma plant supply the character¬ istics of the god of this name. Personification is perhaps carried farthest of all in connexion with Yama, the god of death. Only later does he become an altogether sombre deity. In the Rigveda he is the pioneer of the path to the world beyond; and, although the approach to him is made difficult by reason of many perils, and he himself appears at times to be jealous of human aspira¬ tions after immortality, he is, on the whole, a kindly dispenser of bliss in the realms of the departed. But what is of most importance for our present purpose is the evidence we may gather from the Veda of that growing con¬ ception of unity, joined perhaps with a tendency in a negative direction, which we may take as a definite anticipation of the subsequent general trend of Indian thought. In this connexion we may recall the differences already noted between Greek and Indian thought—the contentment of the latter with vagueness as contrasted with the definite personifications of the former. i 4 VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA The gods of the Veda had the indefiniteness of the natural forces with which they were associated, rather than clearly dis¬ tinguishable characters. Thus their functions are easily inter¬ changeable, and it becomes possible that the individual gods, instead of distributively representing each a particular quality, may represent groups of qualities several of which they possess in common. Then, by an unconscious process of generalization, the view will be entertained that the gods, seeing that they possess common qualities, are one in essence. Attention will gradually be directed beyond the particularity of the gods towards this essence and especially towards that god who is supposed to embody it most completely. One god will thus become supreme in the consciousness of the worshipper, not with the permanent primacy of a definite hierarchy, nor even with the temporary priority which is indicated by the term henotheism. We hesitate to accept unreservedly this favourite term of Max Muller, because it seems to suggest too definitely a comparison of the god selected with other gods who are deliberately disregarded, whereas the true state of the matter seems to be that the nature-form which occupies strikingly the centre of consciousness also occupies more or less vaguely the whole field of consciousness, and the other gods are not simply assigned to a lower rank but left out of account altogether. But what we wish to emphasize is the earnestness and at the same time the vagueness of the religious search after unity. Dissatisfaction with sheer particularity is manifested in various ways. As already indicated, the gods are grouped into three roughly defined classes, and certain of them, such as Agn>, are regarded as having affinity with all three classes. Further, the physical immensity of the deities worshipped, as, e.g^, the sky and the air, will tend to strengthen the feeling of all-pervading- ness and universality . Conceptions , such as that of the All-gods , the gods taken collectively, the 'fellowship of gods V 'the heavenly folk ’, 3 will be laid hold of to break down the barriers of particularity. Also, general creative activity may be personi¬ fied, as in connexion with Prajapati, and another creative deity called Visvakarman. In association with the latter there is developed an interesting distinction between efficient and 1 Cf. Rigveda, VII, 35. 11. a lb. X. 57. 5. VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA 15 material cause, and men are found to be beginning to concern themselves with the original material (corresponding roughly to the Greek ‘hyle’) out of which the ‘sole God ’ has fashioned the earth and the heaven, or with the more poetical form of the question, ‘Whereon he stood when he established all things.’ 1 Perhaps in studying the idea of sacrifice we may reach a fuller appreciation of the Vedic conception of the underlying unity of all things. We have to attempt to replace ourselves in that mental attitude which was, e.g., at the back of the mystery religions in the centuries immediately preceding the Christian era, when the distinction which we modems make between inner and outer, between symbol and fact, was less definite, and when, sensed in a mystical mood, ‘the things of earth are in sympathy with the things of heaven.’ * The sacrifice has to be viewed in its entirety, as an intricate ritualistic system of devices, every detail of which has to be followed with the most scrupulous attention, but which, when properly manipulated, affords the worshipper the opportunity of increasing the hidden forces of the world—what Oldenberg calls the ‘zauberfluidum’ and of ‘tapping’ them for his own advantage or that of his society. The sacrifice is—to adopt a Vedic metaphor—‘the thread spun out to reach the gods’, ‘drawn out with threads on every side, the man extends it, and the man unbinds it; even to the vault of heaven hath he outspun it’. 3 What the worshipper gives to the priest may be conceived as having or acquiring independent value and as added to the fundamental reality of the world. We are not even to regard it as offered to the gods to propitiate them. It is rather a latent power which is older and deeper in the heart of things than the gods themselves, and the latter are invoked only that the sum of conditions may be completed which is necessary for the efficacy of the sacrifice. If all the rules are meticulously followed, the results of the sacrifice will emerge by necessary law, and in this conception of inescapable consequences we may perhaps find the germ of that idea of Rita* or order of the universe, which again becomes 1 lb. 81. 4. . * Cumont, Mysticisme Astral, 242, quoted in Angus, The Mystery Re¬ ligions and Christianity . 3 j Rigveda,yL. 130, 1. 4 Prof. Keith holds that rita originally meant the physical order of the universe. Cf. his Religion and Philosophy of the Veda, 85. x6 VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA the foundation of the doctrine of Karma, so important in subse¬ quent Indian philosophy. The conception of an underlying mysterious force or essence is also deepened metaphysically, and may not unjustifiably be taken as reappearing in the belief in the purusha , the mighty giant who submits to the dismember¬ ment of himself for the sake of the production of the world. Here the sacrifice has become not merely a means of access to the constitutive principle of the universe, but itself that prin¬ ciple. Through the operation of a sacrificial act the world is evolved, and therefore sacrifice is fundamental. We may gain some light also upon the subjectivity and idealism which are characteristic of later Indian thought if we turn back again from the ritual of the sacrifice to the attitude of the worshipper towards it. We must avoid mechanizing the ritual to such an extent as to detach it altogether from the sub¬ jective devotion which seeks to find expression in it, or from the fundamental sense of being in the presence of that mysterium tremendum of which Prof. Otto speaks. If we seek to understand the aspiration of the worshipper, we may conceive it as having at first almost a physical basis, showing itself in that agitated outbreathing which is the accompaniment of great emotion and which some modern psychologists have so closely identified with the actual emotion. The breath may be quite simply con¬ sidered as dispersing and losing itself in the wider atmosphere of the external environment; and, if we can take the further step of imagining the breath as becoming articulate in prayer and can at the same time keep in mind the extremely faint line of demarcation in early thought between the physical and, the psychical or spiritual, we shall find ourselves almost in a position to grasp the idea of the transition by which prayer comes to be regarded as having efficacy in the objective world and as being itself a phase of the fundamental reality of that world. Are we not here also almost within sight of the original underlying conception which may serve to unite the various meanings assigned to the word Btuhtncii The breath of aspira¬ tion which becomes vocal in the spells and incantations of the priests and the chants of the singers and finds symbolic expres¬ sion in some of the material of the ritual, such as the smoke of the sacrificial fire, is discovered also to be not alien to the spirit VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA 17 of man, but of the same substance and character with that spirit. We may see here further the earliest conditions of the emergence of the idea of the Atman , in its meaning of the Vital breath’ of man, which has at the same time the closest connexion with the innermost essence of the objective external world. 1 We do not think it unreasonable to suggest that such fused and confused-Xonceptions as these may be the earliest sources fronTwhich some of the fundamental ideas of Indian philo¬ sophy have emerged and in course of time become gradually crystallized. In more immediate connexion with our present subject we must take account also of what might be described as a process of internalizing the sacrifice. The conception of tapas appears occasionally in the Rigveda. Later on it attracted to itself the idea of mortification or penance, but here it has little more significance than ‘fervour* or ‘heat’, suggesting the sacrifice of devotion which goes on internally and at the same time its kin¬ ship with that power of heat by which the Primal Being genera¬ ted the objective world. However slightly spiritual the con¬ ception may be, it at least serves to turn the attention inwards as well as outwards and to hint at a dawning consciousness that the soul of man may be as important an element in ultimate reality as the underlying forces of the external world. We are encouraged at least to an interpretative use of this psycho¬ physical conception, and prepared, in however slight a degree, for the idea that at the root of existence there is something more than the merely material and that the ultimate essence of the universe may have a spiritual aspect. In view of all this it will seem in no way strange that in the Rigveda we should come across such a flight of metaphysical speculation as is to be found in Book X, 129. 4: Within it at first arose Desire, Which was the primal seed of mind; The root of Being in non-Being Sages Searching by wisdom in the heart discovered? We may also trace the beginnings of a conception of the intrinsic value of knowledge, arising probably out of the idea that the knowledge of the ritual of the sacrifice is of supreme 1 Cf. Das Gupta, 26. 3 Prof. P. D. Shastri’s translation. . . c IS VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA importance as giving access to and control over the mysterious essence of reality. We are here on the lines of an advance to the fuller idea that knowledge itself may constitute reality; and, when the content of the effective knowledge is also taken account of, there emerges the notion of a law or principle hidden beneath the immediate appearances of things. Beneath Being there is something which is not-Being in the ordinary sense of the word, inasmuch as it is not the product of merely ordinary experience. Here there is at least the beginning of a negative procedure of thought. We describe the fundamental reality in negative terms so long as we are looking at it from the empirical point of view, and beside this negation there is the still more significant consciousness that, though we call the ultimate reality non-Being, yet just because it is fundamental, it is also Being in a far more satisfying sense than the ordinary Being of which we are aware in our usual experience. This tendency towards negation as well as towards unity in Vedic thought deserves further consideration by reason of its later importance. Prof. B. K. Shastri points out with emphasis that the fundamental contrast between the Vedic and the Upanishadic attitude to life was that, whereas the former was positive and held to the idea that life was to be lived, the latter was negative and had arrived at the consciousness that 'life must pass through a phase of no life to reach fuller life’. 1 Whence has come this change from the earlier joyous positive of Vedic times? Perhaps one reason may lie just in the subjective effect of this growing sense of unity amongst the gods to which we have referred. As the gods worshipped became fewer in number and at the same rtime more overwhelming by the immensity and extent of their power, the worshippers would inevitably feel farther separated from their deities. Correspondingly, as the world became more rationalized, it would seem to the simpler minds to be emptier of friendly intimate powers, and therefore less desirable— something to be negated. Further, in the attitude to sacrifice which we have attempted to describe, a hint of negative tendency may be discovered. With the associated magic and incantation there is closely connected the idea of ecstasy, of being caught up into a mystical excitement, and of being, therefore, detached 1 B. K. Shastri, p. xii. VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA 19 from the ordinary world. In order to participate, through the sacrifice or other ritual, in the fundamental reality, sometimes conceived of as a semi-magical, almost physical, fluid, the wor¬ shipper is led to depress his faculties as a whole or sacrifice the higher to the lower. The ascetic and orgiastic worshipper is the best magician, if hot the best mystic. But if we depress our higher faculties, it is exceedingly natural to go farther and learn to depreciate or negate our experience as a whole. And to this may be added, on the one hand, that growing consciousness of the complexity and distressfulness of human life with which the dawning—only the faintest dawning, we admit—of the idea of transmigration may have had something to do; and, on the other hand, that disappointment of childlike trust in the first appear¬ ances of things which is the inevitable accompaniment of the natural development of the human mind. It does not take long anywhere for men to learn that the mystery of reality lies deeper than the grasp of our senses. An unmistakably vivid conscious¬ ness of negation is close at hand, whenever reflection emerges, and the speculations to which we have already referred in con¬ nexion with the Rigveda , X. 129, are but the metaphysical aspect of a more popular and universal tendency. There seem, therefore, to be in the Rigveda evidences of a tendency towards unity and of an inclination towards nega¬ tion, sufficient to justify us in finding in the earliest sacred books at least the germs of what were afterwards to be the funda¬ mental ideas of the Vedanta philosophy. It is not necessary to consider the other Vedas to any great extent. The Samaveda and the Yajurveda are for the most part derivative from the Rigveda. The Atharvaveda belongs to a lower level of thought and is rather outside of the main stream of development, although it is not without influence even upon the Upanishads. 1 Its authors, for the most part, inhabit a world of magic and incantation. The great gods have gone from it, and the smaller gods have arrived in the guise of a horde of capricious spirits who require to be placated by the constant performance of intricate rites, which rites themselves are found gradually to be acquiring value as independent forces of the hidden world. 1 Gf. Prof. Ranade, Indian Philosophical Quarterly, 1 .4 and Das Licht vom Osten, 4. 20 VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE VEDA Sin has dropped from the moral to the physical or magical level. It may attach to a man without his consent after the manner of a contagious disease, and the remedy for it is de¬ graded to the same level and consists mainly of magical devices. As Bloomfield says: ‘The notion of expiation extends also to circumstances inherent or accidental, which cannot and do not involve personal responsibility. Expiation assumes the charac¬ ter of cure or correction of inauspicious conditions and accidents.’ 1 It is interesting to observe that in the description of the vratya , or wanderer, found in the fifteenth book of the Atharva¬ veda, Prof. Hauer sees a foreshadowing of the negative attitude and magical claims of the later Yogi, and these may be placed over against a certain philosophical background, however vague and shadowy this may be. The Vratya, who ‘seems to be a kind of Brahmacarin, or, at any rate, one who has entered the Brah- manical community after having been converted from an Aryan but non-Brahmanical tribe’, a manifests a desire to enter into unity with the original ground of things through ascetic ecstasy and a negation of ordinary experience ; and at the same time the claim is made that through magical practices supernatural power may be obtained, and the influence of the soul of the worshipper be extended to the confines of the world. 3 We find also a more elevated, but still very dim, conception of Brahma as the prayer of the worshipped and at the same time the supreme principle of the world d It will therefore not be out of place to suggest that in the Atharvaveda, as well as in the Rigveda, there are indications of that consciousness of funda¬ mental unity, combined with a negative attitude to ordinary experience, which we have already noted in connexion with the earlier book, and which was to become dominant in later thought. To the further development of these ideas in the Upanishads and succeeding literature we shall turn in the next chapter. 1 Bloomfield, Atharva Veda, 84. Ib. 94. 3 Cf. Hauer, in Das Lichtvom Osten, 56. 4 Atharvaveda, V. 1. II ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS IN THE UPANISHADS, THE VEDANTA SUTRAS, THE, GlTA, AND GAUDAPlDA’S KARIKAS I N this chapter we pass to a further stage in Indian thought, at which the development of the fundamental Vedantic ideas (especially those of a consciousness of ultimate unity and an apparent necessity for negation in the search after it) becomes much fuller and more impressive. It is difficult, if not impos¬ sible, to treat of the Upanishads in separation from the Sutras, in which they were summarized—and some would say trans¬ formed—and also the Commentaries in which they were ampli¬ fied and interpreted. They have been described as the kernel of the whole of Post-Vedic Indian philosophy, and it is prover¬ bially difficult to separate the kernel from the remainder of the fruit. Further, the Upanishads have not self-subsistency in the sense that they present us with a clear-cut and definite system of thought which may stand separate examination. From the philosophical point of view they contain^ anticipations rather than completions of doctrine; they are inspirational rather than dogmatic. Their aim, as Prof. Radhakrishnan says, is |‘not so much to reach philosophic truth as to bring peace and free¬ dom to the anxious human spirit’. 1 They make no claim to independence or definiteness or coherence, and therefore sur¬ render themselves easily and unresistingly to later summarizing or expositional treatment. Yet we must not on this account presume to undervalue their importance. They occupy a central position in the history of Indian philosophy. Not only do they, as we have seen, provide materials for future development, but they link themselves closely with the past and gather up its wisdom. They carry forward the tendencies and expound the implicit doc¬ trines discoverable in the Vedic Hymns, and by no means break continuity altogether with the Brahmanas, although they adopt a remarkably free attitude to the authority of the ancient scriptures in general, and undeniably break fresh ground. They mark a tran¬ sition from ritualistic and physical to philosophical and psychical 1 Radhakrishnan, I. 138. 22 ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS categories. As Prof. Das Gupta says: ‘The passage of the Indian mind from the Brahmamc to the Upamshad thought is probably the most remarkable event in the history of philosophic thought.’ 1 On the whole it may be said that their significance is more prospective than retrospective, and it is important for our present purpose to note that, while they are not without influence upon all phases of Indian philosophical thought, and also supply intellectual inspiration to popular religion and to sects both high and low, they have a closer relation to the Vedanta than to any other school of thought. Indeed they are frequently regarded as containing the essence of the Vedanta although frequently, as we have seen, the term Vedanta has both a narrower and a wider interpretation. And in connexion with the r-laim of the later Commentaries to constitute the special basis of the Vedanta, we may notice that the occupation of the commentators would be largely gone, had not the Upamshads supplied them with material for their discussions and a point of departure for their speculations. It may be added also that in the Upanishads themselves the name Vedanta is used as indicative of the philosophy contained in them.* The fundamental meaning of the name Upamshad seems to be derived from the root sad, ‘to sit,’ and upa y ‘near, with the prefix ni, having adverbial and intensive significance; the whole combination thus yielding the idea of ‘sitting very near’ to the teacher and listening intently and respectfully to him. From this it is easy to pass to the idea of the doctrine conveyed by the teacher; and when we take account also of the generally esoteric tendency of the teaching and the exclusive character of the audience, we arrive at the resultant meaning of ‘secret doc¬ trine’. Sankara, however, in his introduction to the. Taittiriya Upamshad, gives an interpretation which has special significance in relation to the character of his philosophy. He favours a derivation from the root sad, ‘to destroy,’ although he does not altogether abandon the idea of ‘nearness’ or ‘approach’. His meaning apparently is that the doctrine would destroyignorance and thus open the way of approach to God. In general, how¬ ever, the conception of ‘secret doctrine ’ would seem to corre¬ spond to the most common use of the term. ■ Das Gupta, 31. 1 Cf. Farquhar, 6o. IN THE UPANISHADS 23 According to tradition, an enormous number of Upanishads was at one time or other in existence. Weber suggests as many as 250, but Prof. Radhakrishnan is content with the more modest number of 108. For our purposes we may confine our attention mainly to the eleven which were commented on by Sankara. These were the Aitareya, Taittirlya, Chhandogya, Brihadaranyaka, Kena, Kathaka, Isa, Mundaka, Svetasvatara, Praina, and JMandukya. But in addition to these, account should also be taken of the Kaushltaki, the Mahanarayana, and the Maitrayana . The oldest and most authoritative Upanishads are in prose, and are pre-Buddhistic and non-sectarian. The earliest group, composed of the Aitareya, the Kaushltaki, the Chhandogya, the Kena, the Taittirlya, and the Brihadaranyaka, were probably in existence by 500 B.c. They are linked very closely to the Brahmanas, but arrive definitely at a philosophical point of view and are indeed more purely speculative than some of the later treatises. Within this group Deussen is inclined to assign temporal priority to the Brihadaranyaka and the Chhan¬ dogya, The second group consists of the Kathaka, the Isa, the Svetasvatara, the Mundaka, and the Mahanarayana ; and the period covered by them is from 50° B - c - to the middle of the third century b.c. There are tendencies in a theistic direction, and emphasis is laid upon the importance of Visnu and Siva. Brahmans appear to have a supremacy to which they had not attained at the period of the earlier works; and, in general, caste distinctions are more rigidly drawn. Greater stress also is laid upon the practice of Yoga, asceticism, and self-discipline. The Svetpivatara, in particular, contains references to the emergence of philosophical schools, and makes use of the technical terms and characteristic doctrines of these schools. To the third group may be assigned the Prasna, the Maitrayana, and the Mandukya. The Maitrayana seems to be contemporary with the earlier form of the Gita, and may be placed in the second century a.d. It contains references to the Sankhya and Yoga philosophies, and its tone is profoundly pessimistic. The Prasna is slightly earlier and the Mandukya slightly later than the Maitrayana . 1 1 Prof. Ranade has recently investigated the problem of Upanishad chronology and places the whole of the Upanishad development between 24 ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS As we consider the transition from the Vedas to the Upani¬ shads, we may refer again to the tendency referred to in the last chapter which indicates a background of growingly sombre character. A full sense of the gravity of the problems which have to be dealt with has been developed, although it is only with difficulty and very gradually that these problems come to be treated from a purely philosophical point of view. The heart is still not sufficiently at leisure from itself to permit of the calmness and detachment necessary for pure speculation. De¬ liverance rather than salvation is the end aimed at, and the remedy for the ills of life is sought in religion rather than in philosophy. The religion of the Vedas was predominantly joyous, but by the time we reach the Upanishads, the sky has become over¬ shadowed. We have already indicated in the last chapter some reasons for the change. We have seen that the tendency away from polytheism in the direction of pantheistic unity may have deepened the shadows which lay upon life. The kindly and familiar deities had withdrawn themselves.from the world, and their erstwhile worshippers felt lonely in the midst of the physical immensities which had served to develop and strengthen the sense of unity. On the other cause to which we referred in passing, a little more may be said. The transmigration theory was gradually introduced into India during this period, probably, though not certainly, from alien sources. At first the doctrine would seem to satisfy the desire for persistence and would have a comforting effect as a relief from the fear that death might be the final .end. But, as the negative tendency grew stronger, and other causes still to be mentioned contributed to this strengthening, and consequently the ideas of escape and deliverance came more and more to occupy the centre of consciousness, these ideas 1200 and 600 b.c. He divides the principal Upanishads into the following five groups, with a rough, but by no means strict, chronological sequence: I. Brihaddranyaka and Chhdndogya. II. Jsd and Kena. III. Aitareya, Taittiriya, and Kaushttaki, IV. KdphakatMundaka^ndMdndiikya. V. Prasna, Maitrayana, and Mandukya. Of. ‘The Background of Upanishadic Philosophy", in the Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. I, p. 5. IN THE UPANISHADS 25 would again find reinforcement in the thought of a succession of lives. Continuance of existence under such conditions would simply be an additional source of misery. Escape becomes a more difficult and more hopeless problem when a practically unending series of lives has to be reckoned with; and the pessimism which has attached itself to the experiences of a single life becomes infinitely increased. Various other causes, not of course peculiar to India, may have contributed to the darkening of the background. The deadening effect of despotism, with its accompanying depres¬ sing contrasts between wealth and poverty, came to be obvious causes at a later period, and there may have been anticipations of such conditions even in the centuries under review. The effect of the climate of the plains of India may also be noted. As the number of centuries increased which separated the Aryan settlers from the period of their immigration, the lassi¬ tude engendered by sub-tropical conditions may have dimin¬ ished their zest for life, may have induced a mood of passive acquiescence rather than of struggle, and disposed them in general to seek for deliverance rather than victory. Throughout the Upanishads we find indications of this sombre background, and indications of a perplexed, almost pathetic, yearning after deliverance. In the Kathaka Upanishad 1 we are told that ‘the wise man ceases to grieve when he knows the distinction of the Self from the senses’. Human experience is found to be of a fleeting and unsatisfactory character, pre¬ dominantly painful. It is repeatedly suggested that the state we are to flee from is one of misery, and the object of our striving is to free ourselves from old age or death or grief. ‘There is no bliss in anything finite.’ z In drawing attention to this pessimistic background we are not, of course, forgetful of the general consideration that it is in a ‘divine discontent’ and a dissatisfaction with the actual that all philosophy originates. If, however, the preliminary view of the problems to be solved is excessively gloomy, this frequently exercises a demoralizing influence upon the solutions arrived at. Philosophy comes to be regarded as providing a means of release rather than a system of constructive thought. Instead 1 II. 6. 7. a Cf, Chhandogya 27 . VII. 26. 1. 26 ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS of being occupied with a patient investigation of the world which has presented the problems, attention is diverted from this world, and the rapidity with which a solution can be arrived at becomes all-important. The mind is thus left with insufficient freedom for pure and independent speculation, and, under the urgent influence of religious motives and practical needs, arguments are accepted which are admittedly not cogent from an intellectual point of view. Under the influence of the idea of escape, recourse may be had, e.g., to the doctrine of two orders of knowledge, so related that instead of the lower order gradually yielding up its problems and contradictions for solu¬ tion on the higher plane, a quick transition is permitted from the one to the other, with consequences that are disastrous to philosophical consistency. Dr. Hauer definitely finds in causes of this sort one explanation of the negative character of Upani- shad philosophy. He holds that, if the identification of the human soul with the world-principle had been purely meta¬ physical, this would have led to an affirmatory spiritualizing of the world. But this, however, has been expressed only occasionally in the Upanishads, and for the most part the religio-mystical attitude has led to that denial of the world which was an anticipation or accompaniment of Buddhistic negation. If the sense of need had not been so clamant and urgent, the character of the solution would probably have been different. 1 On the other hand, while it seems necessary to stress in some degree the pessimistic character of the primary attitude, we must not overlook an actual and vigorous speculative interest. The Upanishads are dominated by a sense of a mystery which is attractive as well as terrifying, and by an intense desire to penetrate this mystery. Intellectual curiosity is a strong motive alongside of the desire for deliverance. ‘Tell us what there is in the great hereafter, 5 says Nachicetas in the Kathaka Upanishads and one of the searchers after truth in the ChhandogyaUpanishad is asked whether he has ‘sought for the instruction by which the Unheard becomes heard, the Unintelligible intelligible, and the Unknown known 5 . 3 In the same Upanishad one of the teachers 1 Cf. Hauer, in -Das Licht vom Osten, 91. 3 I. 1. 29. 3 VI, 3. 5. IN THE UPANISHADS 27 is said to have shown his pupil ‘the back of the other side of darkness’, 1 and the oft-repeated refrain of the Bnhadaranyaka Upanishad, indicative of the spirit of the Upanishads as a whole, is ‘Lead me from darkness into light, from the unreal to the Real’. The very name ‘Upanishad’, if we adopt the prevailing in¬ terpretation, indicates a tendency to speculative construction. Further, the state from which deliverance is sought is described in an intellectual manner, not merely as a state of misery but as a state of error. The inquiries of which the results are set forth are, moreover, undertaken at a period of life when the active duties of the householder are supposed to be com¬ pleted, and the seeker after truth is no longer disturbed by the cares of the world and is free to enter upon a period of quiet contemplation and study of the ultimate mysteries. Also it has to be remembered that, at the period of the great Upanishads, there was, perhaps, greater freedom from the bonds of traditional authority than at any other period in the history of Indian thought. The authority of the Vedas was still strong, but it was not so excessive as to necessitate a purely scholastic procedure and an incessant repetition of tra¬ ditional ideas. The Upanishads link themselves to previous thought through their great interest in the mysteries and power of the sacrifice, in the consideration of which we have found one of the earliest hints of a sense of underlying unity. In the sacrifice the wor¬ shipper feels himself to be in contact with the hidden forces of the .world, with the power which is even more fundamental than the power of the gods. The Upanishads lay increased emphasis upon the monistic suggestions which are here in¬ volved, but make a more definite and more sustained transition from the external to the internal, and from the objective to the subjective. They lay hold upon such suggestions as we find in Rigveda, I. 164. 4, ‘Where was the vital breath, the blood, the Self (Atman) of the world?’ They place full stress upon the double implication, both physical and spiritual, contained in the notions of Brahman and Atman, and upon the internalizing of the sacrifice through the help of the conception of tapas. Indeed I VII. 26. 2. 28 ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS the possible identification of Brahman and Atman becomes almost a central principle of investigation and the tendency in the direction of a negation of anything that hinders this identifi¬ cation is discovered to be greatly strengthened. The two main aspects of Upanishad thought may indeed be stated as (i) a negative movement towards a denial of the particularity of the world of our ordinary experience, and (2) a more positive move¬ ment towards the identification of the human spirit and the divine, governed by the hope of reaching an absolute unity. It is impossible, however, to separate these two movements, save for the temporary purposes of exposition. We have found the germ of a negative movement in the Vedas, perhaps especially in the hardly more than physical idea of a participation in a semi-magical fluid. When transferred to the subjective side of the relationship, and plunged in a psychical atmosphere of ecstasy, this same tendency reappears in the depression of faculties usually regarded as higher, so that the emotional aspiration which remains may obtain contact with the physical hidden energy. But, as we have seen, the denial of the higher activities, which is thus suggested and encouraged, may very easily extend to a depreciation of our powers of ordinary experience in general, and it is by no means easy to eradicate this negative tendency when once it has manifested itself. We have already hinted at some of the probable causes of the transition from the outer to the inner. We have noted the growing importance even in the Vedas of a knowledge of the sacrifice. It was thought to be exceedingly dangerous to make any mistake in the performance of the elaborate ritual, and, consequently, meticulously exact knowledge was regarded as placing enormous power in the hands of those who had acquired it. Emphasis was transferred from the action performed in the sacrifice to knowledge of how to perform it. Further, there was a tendency in the direction of identifying the knower with that which he knew. The subjective consciousness of the priest would thus be conceived of as having effective contact with the mysterious power of the sacrifice with which he had to deal; and the question would naturally arise as to whether the funda¬ mental power or essence of things might not be found in con- IN THE UPANISHADS 29 sciousness just as well as in the objects with which it was so intimately connected. 1 But when attention is thus directed internally to conscious¬ ness, it is important that this should be left as simple and un¬ trammelled as possible. If it is felt as a power, its effectiveness must not be allowed to be unduly distributed. The immediate data of the senses, with their resulting disturbing intrusions of objects in space and time, must not be allowed to distract us. If we are to reach the fontal unity, we must attempt to crush together the details of the world, so that, coalescing, they may fit into this unity. Differences of value must be disregarded, and things of both higher and lower importance must be negated. He who thinks is one, and therefore the victory must remain with unity. 2 All change and all associated plurality must be regarded as a matter of 'names and forms 5 . By the medieval nominalists of Europe names were held to give fictitious reality to general notions; but in the Upanishads it is to individual objects that they give this fictitious support. We need not at this stage stop to inquire into the degree of fictitiousness thus involved. It is sufficient to say that naming is the other side of an individua¬ lizing tendency the effect of which is unreal if the individuals thus constituted are taken as separate from the whole, but which may have a certain amount of justification if the unity of the whole is at the same time firmly grasped. The attainment of the conception of the merely nominal character of particulars ought, however, at least to have the result of diminishing our interest in these particulars, decreasing our centrifugal desires, and thus contributing to our peace of mind and subjective sense of unity. It comes to this, that if we are to deny the world we must have some metaphysical justification for so doing. The world as a whole cannot properly be denied unless it is found to be of an illusory character. As we shall see later, it is not easy to decide how far the Upanishads themselves can be taken to support a doctrine of illusoriness, but there are at least anticipa¬ tions of the conception of may a. In the Svetasvatara Upanishads e.g., we read, 'The one God regulates nature and the Self. By meditating on Him the world-illusion is completely removed. , * Cf. Hauer, op. tit >, 86, a Cf. Mdndukya U. II. 25. 3 I. 10. 3 o ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS Our deliverance is wrought through the destruction of our ignorance, by rising from apara vidya (lower knowledge) to para vidya (higher knowledge), and we can reach the best under¬ standing of the position if we formulate the conception that the term avidya (ignorance) may be applied not only to the mistaken mental attitude of the knower, but also to what is known. It involves not only the negative idea usually associated with ignorance, but also the more positive idea -of ‘false knowledge’; in other words, it includes not only empirical ignorance but empirical knowledge. From this the transition is easy to regarding avidya as a cosmi- cal principle. It becomes the source not only of our belief in an ordinary world but of the ordinary world in which we believe. The world of ordinary experience is explained by a principle which suggests a negative way of dealing with this world, and, consequently, a depreciatory valuation of it. And this cosmic principle gains metaphysical importance by being more or less vaguely related to God. The Svetasvatara Upanishad describes it as ‘the own power of God concealed by its emanation’. 1 The exact relation of this cosmic power to God and the metaphysical standing of its products give rise to some of the most important problems of later Yedantic philosophy. The central problem is just whether the things of the ordinary world are altogether to be deprived of reality, or whether only their particularity is to be denied. But whatever conclusion may later be arrived at, we may agree that there is in any case sufficient opportunity for such denial or depreciation as will afford a discipline prepara¬ tory for the second phase of the Upanishad philosophical move¬ ment, viz. the identification of the Self of the individual and the Self of the Universe; and to this we must now turn. The principle of procedure is that in discovering the deepest nature of our own selves, we shall also discover the fundamental nature of the universe. ‘The light which shines above the heaven, higher than all, higher than everything, beyond which there are no other worlds, that is the same light which is within' man.’ 2 All our difficulties, both theoretical and practical, come from our failure to reach this identification, and the attainment of it ought to be the object of all our searching. Here is the i I, 5, 3 Chhandogya 17 , 111 . 15. 7. IN THE UPANISHADS secret of the universe, and here is the foundation of our peace. ‘He who knows Brahman is Brahman.' ‘That which is that subtle essence (the root of all) in it all that exists has its self. It is the True. It is the Self, and thou, O Svetaketu, art it.' 1 The fundamental formula is tat tvarh asi —‘That Thou art'— a formula which expresses succinctly the equation of the indi¬ vidual self with the Universe, and of the Universe with the Self in the highest sense, the result being a pure undifferenced unity, or, at least, a unity in regard to which all differences are on the point of being transcended. Another formula with much the same meaning is aham Brahma asmi , ‘I am Brahman.' Sometimes the formula has been mistakenly compared to the Greek yvcoOi aeavrov, but we must carefully notice that while the Greek formula may inculcate a thorough study of the nature of the individual self, the Upanishad formula is con¬ cerned with the conception that the true self of each individual, when thoroughly known, is discovered to be not at all indi¬ vidual. As soon as we reach the essence of the individual self, the equation of it to the universal Self, and the identification of Atman and Brahman, is found to be inevitable. The two terms are recognized as reciprocal. Probably the interpretation of their relation afterwards adopted by Sankara may be accepted also as giving a true account of the Upanishad position. ‘Brahman’, he says, ‘denotes the term to be defined (viseshyam) and Atman that which defines it (viseshanan), that by Brahman the limitation implied in Atman is removed, and by Atman the conception of Brahman as an (external) divinity to be wor¬ shipped is condemned.' 3 Dr. Hauer of Tubingen takes much the same view. ‘Thus came about the mingling of the two ideas, to the advantage of both. Brahman becomes wholly dissociated from the realm of the magical, and the Atman attains infinity.' 3 We reach this identification by passing through various stages, and we may first of all trace the process as it takes place in the experience of the individual who is striving to reach the inner essence of his soul. The exposition may be based on Chhandogya Upanishad VIII. We are first asked to consider 1 Chhandogya U, VI. 8. 7. Cf, also VI. 9.4; VI. xo. 3, &c. z Cf. Sankara’s Commentary on the Chhandogya U. y reproduced in Deussen, P. U. 86. 3 Op, dt, y p. 91. 32 ANTICIPATIONS OF YEDANTIC IDEAS the stage of ordinary waking life, and Prajapati, in conversation with Indra, explains that the Self is The person who is seen in the eye’, i.e. the ordinary bodily or material self (Vaisvanara) dwelling in a cosmical environment to which the name Virat is given. Indra, however, is not satisfied with this explanation, and his attention is next turned to the dreaming state, in which only the mind is active, in more or less complete inde¬ pendence of the body. To this corresponds the cosmical world- power, Hiranyagarbha, or soul of the world. We should notice here the complete reversal of our usual experience; as a rule we put the waking state above the dreaming state, but in this scheme the latter occupies the place of greater honour. Yet, even at this stage of dreaming, the soul has not got rid of the limiting conditions of individuality. Although it ‘moves about happy in dreams, immortal, fearless V it is yet dependent on bodily experiences for the materials presented to its conscious¬ ness. Hence we must rise to the third stage of dreamless sleep, at which we attain to independence of the environment and even of our own individuality, and become enfolded in the, prajna Atman—the true self, the universal subject of thought. In Kaushltaki Upanishad III. 3 we are helped to understand this by a comparison with a dying man and the gradual infolding of his faculties. All the distractions which have disturbed us are merged in an absolute unity, and no wishes except the wish for the self are left. The cosmical parallel of this stage is said to be Is vara, but here we must conceive of Isvara in his most indefinite phase, almost before the cosmical ignorance has begun to operate. Yet, especially in the later Upanishads, there are hints that even this state of dreamless sleep is not the highest stage. It is too negative and is also transient and liable to interruptions breaking in from waking experience. The highest stage cannot therefore be left dependent on what might be called the accident of deep sleep, but must be assigned a more positive basis in profound contemplation which we may voluntarily induce and can secure against disturbance. We desire to reach a state of being which shall be ‘coincident with absolute wake- fulness’, and shall in a measure approach the self-luminousness * Cf. Chhandogya U. VIII. 80. IN THE UPANISHADS 33 of Brahman. This highest state, or turiya, cannot, of course, be described, because of the nearness of its approach to Brahman, and because Brahman is indescribable. In any case the highest experience of identity is self-sufficing with a satisfaction that we could only lessen by any attempt to put it into words. Sometimes even a fifth state, unmanly is hinted at, which has been described as the fourth state 4 arrived at maturity 5 . In a slightly more detailed way the soul's ascent to God is described under the figure of the five sheaths (.kosa ), and in this connexion also we have the same mingling of psychological and cosmical conception. There is (1) the annamaya sheath, or sheath of food, at which stage the self is identified with the material body. Then comes (2) the prdnamaya sheath, or sheath of breath, in which we reach fullness of physical life, and the organism is regarded in its dynamical rather than in its statical aspect. This life fills the outer sheath, and is to be regarded as akin to the universal life or world-force. In penetrating to (3) the manomaya sheath, we enter the psychical region. But we remain at the level of the purely empirical self, and are more concerned with the contents of consciousness than with the activity of underlying them. We are still entirely dependent on external impressions ; religiously we are under the control of authority, and ethically we aim merely at private and personal ends. So, (4) we must transcend this purely empirical level and reach, through the vijndnamaya sheath, to the self that is above particular impressions and desires. We must lay hold of the Reason that underlies all our mental activity and attain the understanding that this Reason is not merely individual, but universal. Yet, though this is the highest point which the intellect or reason can reach, it is not the central reality itself. We are still under the conditions of duality; we still distinguish ourselves from the objects of our thought. We cannot be satisfied until we penetrate the (5) anandamaya kosa , or sheath of bliss, where subject and object are one, where individuality is destroyed and absorption is complete, where we close with all we flow from, soul with soul. Now nothing remains but Brahman, grasped by us through pure intuition, and Brahman is fullness of joy. We have traced the stages of this intense and earnest search p ■■ 34 ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS after unity. The process seems to have been very largely nega¬ tive, and what degree of reality may still attach to the experiences of the various stages will have to be further discussed in connexion with the final interpretations of the Vedanta. The question immediately presents itself whether even at the end we have reached reality or only blank nothingness? We may say at once that we have not reached an Absolute which can be described through the forms of sense-experience or even through the categories of the understanding. Brahman stands too near to us for characterization; we cannot stand apart from Him and view Him as an object. Nor should we attempt to do so, for Sankara’s later warning against ascribing subjective qualities to the object seems but an echo of Brihadaranyaka Upanishad III. 4. 2, ‘Thou couldst not see the true seer of sight, thou couldst not hear the true hearer of hearing, nor perceive the perceiver of perception, nor know the knower of knowledge. This is thy Self who is within all.’ To impose predicates upon Brahman is only a temporary expedient similar to the operation of the goldsmith who mixes alloy with the gold so that he may work upon it; and the confusion which results when we attempt to apply finite predicates will open our eyes to their inadequacy. Contradictory predicates, though both true in a limited sense, should finally be regarded as cancelling each other, and so setting us free for higher operations of speculation. We may, e.g., apply the predicate of Being, but we shall find that this is not Being in the empirical sense. ‘Thought’ in Brahman is not the mental activity to which we ordinarily apply the term. The consciousness ascribable to Brahman cannot include the relation of duality of subject and object. Brahman is neither internally nor externally cognitive, neither conscious nor unconscious. 1 All that we can say from the ordinary point of view about the mental character of Brahman is that Brahman is at least not lower than thought. The predi¬ cate of ‘bliss’ also is largely negative. It means complete deliverance from what is not bliss, complete freedom from the distractions, confusions, and miseries arising from our con¬ nexion with the empirical world. Thus, in the failure of attempts to describe the Absolute of *MdndukyaU.V,j . IN THE UPANISHADS 35 the Upanishads, we seem to be compelled to lay our hands upon our mouths and take refuge altogether in negation, in the formula neti, neti —‘it is not so, it is not so.’ But it must not be thought that we have reached the negation of Brahman himself. In theory, at least, we have reached ultimate Reality and not ultimate nothingness. It is true, of course, that some will say that it is only in theory that we have escaped negation, and that, in passing from the knowable to the Unknowable, we have entered the realm of blank darkness and silence from which there is no return. We are not yet in a position to decide whether or not this criticism is justified, but surely all would agree that even if the intellect may fail in the adequate expression of religious truth, this does not mean utter failure, but that above the workings of the intellect we must postulate the flashing insight of in¬ tuition. What intuition can give us it may not be possible to put into words, but yet, notwithstanding our silence, we may be in contact with the deepest reality. Most competent scholars refuse to admit that the Upanishads reach only negation. Prof. Radhakrishnan, e.g., says, ‘It was not the intention of the Upanishads to make of the deeper self an abstract nothingness. It is the fullest reality, the completest consciousness, and not a mere negative calm, untroubled by any unrest and unpolluted by any blot or blemish. The logic of thought has in it a negative movement, where it rises by repudiation of the finite, but this is only a stage in the onward march. By the negative process the self has to recognize that its essence is not in its finitude or self-sufficiency. By the positive method it finds its true self, in the life and being of all. All things exist within this true self.’ 1 It is possible that this interpretation is correct, but the question of its validity is just the main problem of the later developments of the Vedanta philosophy. , Meanwhile, it is sufficient to note that in the Upanishads themselves there are, placed alongside of the negative move¬ ment, certain tendencies in the direction of a more positive rehabilitation of the world of ordinary experience. Those who were most persistent in denying the reality of the world, found, nevertheless, that they had to make some efforts to live wi thin 1 Radhakrishnan, 163. D Z 36 ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS it, or at least to adjust their thought to it. Further, as Prof. Radhakrishnan puts it, ‘The spiritual sense of the masses could not be satisfied by these abstractions of the Upanishads.’ 1 They, and some of the philosophers along with them, were dissatisfied by a conclusion so remote from ordinary fulfilments of human aspiration, and by the somewhat artificial methods by which it was indicated that such a conclusion could be practically reached. The aoidya theory also contained within it certain disconcerting inconsistencies. Thus it came about that by means of symbols and metaphors they sought to re-establish the ordinary world', whilst yet, by emphasis upon the fact that they were only symbols, something of the essential character of the idealistic position could be retained. When, however, sym¬ bols were once admitted, it was very difficult to select any which did not implicitly suggest the reality of the external world. Even the metaphor of the Self as that into which all things pass ‘as the ocean is the one thing into which all waters flow’ 2 implies the reality of' the rivers both before and after they enter. Brahman is said to penetrate the world as the salt per¬ vades the water, but surely the water has also a reality, other¬ wise the salt could not pervade it. In fact, the symbols are in general found to be expressive of a doctrine of emanation, and much of the cosmology of the Upanishads is devoted to setting forth the various stages of emanation. Thus, in regardboth to the characterization of the ultimate unity and its expression in the world of concrete existences, we may say that the Upanishads at least leave it an open question whether they insist on a negatively idealistic position or permit a positive affirmation of the world. There can be no doubt, however, that the fundamental concept of the Upanishads is that of unity, and the prevailing motive is a search after this unity, discoverable as akin to the soul of man. As Dr. Barnett puts it, ‘The principle of the Upanishads is monism, spirituality, and human likeness.’3 A short note may be added as to the conditions under which, from the point of view of the Upanishads, this relentless search after unity was undertaken. It is said in the Kd.th.aka Upanishad J. 5. 14, that ‘the path to the Self is hard, like the sharp edge of > Radhakrishnan, 275. * Cf. Brihadaranyaka D\ IV. 5. 12. 3 Cf. Brahma-Knowledge , 19. IN THE UPANISHADS 37 a razor’. The conditions may be divided into external and internal. As regards the former, we may note that the aspirant must belong to the proper class. Those who venture to teach the Vedas to &udras are threatened with terrible penalties. Women are, as a rule, excluded from the privileges of the teaching. Even Yajnavalkya, after subjecting his wife to long discussions on the subject of immortality, leaves her behind when he goes into the forest, evidently not considering that she is worthy to accompany him. The meaning of Upanishad which is generally accepted, viz. 'secret doctrine’, suggests a body of truth which is to be communicated only to a very few. Some¬ times the circle is still further narrowed through the idea that the teacher has a monopoly in certain doctrines, and his rights seem to be handed on from one generation to another by a kind of apostolical succession. In any case, instruction by a teacher was considered absolutely necessary, and this instruction was spread over a long period. The conditions no doubt ministered to the development of many estimable qualities, but can hardly have been altogether favourable to intellectual freedom and healthy criticism. Besides the authority of the teacher, we have to take account also of the authority of the Vedas and, in general, of the close¬ ness of the relations by which the Upanishads were linked with the past. Opinion on this point seems to have been by no means uniform amongst the authors of the Upanishads. The Chhan- dogya Upanishad 1 suggests that the Vedas need be studied only in the odd moments left over from other tasks; and the older Upanishads generally seem to regard them merely as means to an end, which means might be discarded when the end had been attained. In the later Upanishads, however, as the influence of the Brahmans increased, the study of the Vedas acquired greater importance, and the attitude taken up towards them came to resemble very much that of the medieval European scholastics in relation to the stereotyped doctrines of the Church. Another condition which might be described as external— inasmuch as it was not under the control of the aspirant—is connected with a vague doctrine of election. The searcher after 1 VIII. is. 38 ANTICIPATIONS OF VED ANTIC IDEAS truth has to take up a more or less passive attitude in reference to the Self. He not only searches for the Self, but it might also be said to search for him and to choose him. The Svetdsvatara Upanishad, e.g., says that knowledge is 4 by grace of the Creator 5 , 1 and the Kdthaka Upa?iishad teaches that the Self ‘is attainable by him alone whom it chooses 5 . 2 It should be noted, however, that, although Deussen, Max Muller, and Pandit Tattvabhu- shan approve of this translation, Gough favours a translation which indicates a more active attitude—‘If he chooses the Self, it is attainable by him. 5 As regards internal conditions, it may be said generally that success in the quest is dependent on moral conditions. The soul must be purified from vagrant desires, and works must be relegated to their proper place. The short Isa Upanishad con¬ tains the prayer, ‘Keep us free from crooked evil, and we shall offer thee praise 5 , and the Brihadaranyaka Upanishad de¬ scribes the ideal student as one who has become ‘quiet, subdued, satisfied, patient, collected 5 . Cf. also the Kdthaka Upanishad II. 24, ‘He who has not first turned away from frivolity, who is restless and uncollected, in whose heart there is not peace, cannot through searching reach him. 5 There is great diversity of opinion as to the place of works in the religious and philosophic quest, but on the whole the view seems to be that works, though necessary as a preparatory discipline, cannot have permanent value. They lead only to a lower and transitory felicity; they do not ‘cling to a man 5 . Yet there is apparent not infrequently a fear lest men may be tempted to conclude prematurely that the preparatory stage has been passed, and it is indicated that those who fall into this danger enter into greater darkness of soul than those who trust to works alone. 3 We should also remember that when we are exhorted to ‘cease from works 5 and betake ourselves entirely to contemplation, the contemplation which is enjoined is not entirely passive, but is frequently strongly contrasted with mental inactivity and sluggishness of mind. 1 111. 20. a II. 23. 3 Cf. Isa U. 12 and Brihadaranyaka U. IV. 4. 10. IN THE VEDANTA SUTRAS 39 Vedanta Sutras The Vedanta Sutras, otherwise known as the Brahma Sutras, or the Sarirdka Sutras (which latter term signifies that they are concerned with the ‘embodied soul’ of Brahma), are regarded as constituting, along with the Upanishads and the Gita, the Prasthanatraya, or ‘Canon’ of the Vedanta. We are at once faced with the problem as to whether the Sutras can be con¬ sidered, as it were, in their own right. As has been pointed out above ’‘’they had a place in the development of Indian philo¬ sophy’ which is strikingly suggestive of the character of that development. They were intended to be a collection of short sayings in which the essence of the Vedanta was to be preserved; or, as Sankara puts it—in a phrase which is. non-committal as regards their determinative value—‘they string together the flowers of the Vedanta passages’. Above all they aim at brevity. Their compilers are twitted with ‘delighting as much in the saving of a short vowel as in the birth of a son , and Dr. Mac- donnell says further, ‘The prose in which these works are com¬ posed is so compressed that the wording of the most laconic telegram would appear diffuse compared with it.’ 2 The Sutras, as we have seen, served the purpose of a compressed material suitable for memorizing, and were the foundation for notes of discussions continued through the centuries in the different schools. As we have also seen, they would be difficult of under¬ standing even for those who took part in the discussions and almost completely unintelligible for others. Various opinions are held on the question as to whether the unintelligibility was intentional or not. It may have been due to deliberate esoteric- ism, a determination to keep the precious truths sacrosanct from the so-called unworthy. Deussen holds that the obscurity can¬ not ‘be sufficiently explained either by striving after brevity or a predilection for characteristic ways of expression. Rather must we admit that the composer or composers intentionally sought after obscurity, in order to make their work of treating the secret doctrine of the Veda inaccessible to all those to whom it was not opened up by the explanations of a teacher.’ 3 But it ! p< 2 Sanskrit Literature, 56. 3 Deussen, S. V. 27. 4 o ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS is possible also that the obscurity may have been the result merely of that spirit of academic aloofness which steals over all close corporations of scholars and renders them almost unaware even of the existence of those who are outside the privileged groups and unaccustomed to its peculiar terminology. But whatever the motive may be, there is no doubt about the obscurity. Words are omitted without the slightest compunc¬ tion, and even those that are left are not key-words to the cryptic sentences, but merely mnemonics, serving the purpose of assisting the memory of a well-drilled pupil rather than of illuminating the understanding of an investigator coming freshly to his task. Thus the Sutras served mainly as lines of communication between the old and the new, securing by their traditional prestige and their compact serviceableness that the old should, to a large extent, dominate the new, but yet, because of their merely schematic character, permitting, within certain limits, considerable variety and development in interpretation. From this it comes about that although, taking advantage of the opportunities afforded by mere outlines, the Sutras may selec¬ tively omit certain aspects of doctrine and emphasize others, and thus acquire a distinctive character of their own, yet for the most part their vagueness and unintelligibility will lead to their surrender into the hands of commentators. If the Sutras cannot be understood without the help of these later expositions, it follows that the work of the commentators who explain will gradually acquire greater importance than that which they are explaining. For this reason it might seem hardly worth while to attempt at this stage any detailed discussion of the Sutras themselves, and advisable to pass on at once to the dominating commentaries and view the Sutras merely in the light of the ostensible expositions. Yet it would be a mistake to go too far in this direction. We have spoken of the Sutras as lines of communication, and we might be satisfied with a barren metaphor of this kind if we could establish a definite starting-point of the lines, and also a definite ending. We could then indicate the main purport of the Sutras by giving as full an account as possible of the data from which they proceed and of the final interpretations in IN THE VEDANTA SUTRAS 41 which their doctrines are consummated. But this is just what we cannot do, and the problem is much more complex. The Upanishads, which the Sutras set out to interpret, are very far from presenting a definite system of doctrine allowing of only one possible summary. As a matter of fact the Upanishads supply material for many different systems of philosophy and for very varying interpretations, and it cannot be decided a priori which system or which interpretation the Sutras are likely to favour. Moreover, when we look to the other end of the line of communications, we find that the Sutras are suscep¬ tible of, and have actually been given, many different interpre¬ tations, and that, therefore, it is impossible to select any one commentary, as, e.g., Sankara’s, and say dogmatically that it may be accepted without question as the only continuation of the real meaning of the Sutras. Deussen, indeed, says without hesitation that Sankara is throughout in agreement with the Sutras , but other scholars, possessing equal if not greater authority, declare that Sankara and the Sutras contradict each other on many important points, and that other commentators, as, e.g., Ramanuja, give more trustworthy expositions of the essential meaning of the Sutras. In view of such difference of opinion, therefore, it would seem necessary to attempt a slight and purely provisional characterization of the Sutras in order that we may be able at a later stage to place Sankara and Ramanuja in a proper relation to them. Deussen describes the relation of the Sutras to the Upani¬ shads as similar to that of Christian dogmatics to the New Testament. 1 This comparison is perhaps rather misleading in view of the conciseness of the Sutras and the tendency to expansion manifested by at least some systems of Christian dogmatics. The comparison suggested by Dr. Carpenter would seem to be more serviceable. He says, 'The Sutras have a dis¬ tinct resemblance to the books of “Sentences” which served as the foundation of theological teaching in the medieval schools of Europe. They were based on Scripture and the Fathers, and ran a parallel course in time with Indian production, leading off with those of Isodore of Seville (560-636). Most famous was the collection of Peter the Lombard, Magister Sententiarum y 1 Cf. Deussen, S. V. 2,1. 42 ANTICIPATIONS OF YEDANTIC IDEAS whose work was completed between 1145 an< i II 5 °> * n f° ur books dealing with God, the creation, the virtues, the seven sacraments, and the “last things”. It gained immense popularity and became the accredited text-book in almost every theological school. Numberless commentaries were devoted to its eluci¬ dation, no fewer than 180 being written in England.’ 1 . The dates of the Sutras have been very variously estimated. Deussen 2 puts the date very late. He lays great stress on the connexion between Badarayana (the reputed author of the Sutras) and Jaimini, the author of the most important book on the Karma Mimarhsa. Badarayana and Jaimini repeatedly quote each other by name, and this suggests to Deussen that what we now have is a composite work edited by Vyasa, who might possibly be connected by a kind of apostolical anticipa¬ tion with Sankara, and be only some two hundred years earlier than his commentator (who flourished about the ninth century). Thus the date which Deussen favours would be about a.d. 600. Deussen also lavs stress on the priority of the Gita to the Sutras, on which point, however, he is definitely contradicted by Max Muller ,3 who argues that the apparent quotations from the Gita may well be from other sources, and holds as his general opinion that Badarayana is not dependent on any authorities which can be assigned to a period later than the Christian era. Jacobi dates the Sutras between a.d. 200 and a.d. 450.4 p ro f. S. N. Das Gupta pushes the date back to the second century B.c. He holds that an earlier date is impossible because of the references to many other systems contained in the Sutras. But he would fain go farther, and it is almost with reluctance that he consents to so late a date. Some Indian scholars would go as far back as 500 B.c. It seems necessary, however, to leave room for a considerable amount of development between the date of the early Upanishads and the composition of the Sutras. Thibaut holds that the ‘collection of Sutras was preceded by a long series of preparatory literary efforts of which they merely represent the highly condensed outcome’ .5 Dr. Farquhar is in agreement with Thibaut, and also takes the view that a long succession of scholars is behind the author, the names of seven 1 Carpenter, 299. * Cf. S. V, 21. Cf.J. A* O. S. $ 1911, p. 201. 5 3 Miiller, S. S. m. Cf. S. B . E. XXXIV, p. xii. IN THE VEDANTA SUTRAS 43 of these appearing in the work itself. 1 He also offers the more particular view that a compendium was in existence about the beginning of our era, and that this was the precursor of the Sutras as we now have them. In this way he would explain the reference in the Gita to ‘well thought out verses of Brahma Sutras’, 3 and incidentally dispose of Prof. Das Gupta’s conten¬ tion that the Brahma Sutras (as we have them) were already regarded as an authoritative work by the dualists and therefore might quite naturally be referred to in the Gita. On the whole, the evidence points to a comparatively late date, certainly not earlier than the Christian era. But, whatever the exact date may be, there are traces of the existence already of many diverse views. References are found, e.g., to three different views of the relation of the soul to God; one, associated with the name of Asmarathya, that the soul is neither absolutely different from God nor absolutely the same; a second, associated with Audu- lomi, that the soul, while temporarily different, is by release altogether merged in Brahman; and a third, associated with Kasakritsna, that the soul is absolutely non-different from Brahman. 3 In regard to the special teaching of the Sutras it may be said that they treat the Upanishads with great reverence, and, like them, emphasize the religious and moral conditioning of philo¬ sophical inquiry. 4 On the whole their tendency is towards a dualistic and theistic modification of the strictly monistic position which may be taken as fundamental in the Upanishads, and which was afterwards more strongly developed by Sankara. They favour the interpretation afterwards adopted by Ramanuja rather than Sankara’s own doctrine. They do not draw a firm distinction between two orders of knowledge or between a Brahman without qualities and a Brahman with qualities, and they show little sympathy with an extreme interpretation of the maya doctrine. Whether this tendency in a theistic direction is due to the influence of the Gita or itself contributed to the particular character of the latter, will, of course, be decided differently according to the view taken of the chronological 1 Cf. Farquhar, 126. 2 Gita, XIII. 4 -. 3 Cf. Thibaut, S. B.E. XXXIV, p. xix, and a corresponding paragraph m Farquhar, 128. 4 Cf. Sutras, I. 1. 1. 44 ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS relation between the Sutras and the Gita. It seems probable that they belonged to much the same school of thought, and general considerations at least prepare us for the view that Sankara, and perhaps one or two of his immediate predecessors, found it necessary to give expression to a reaction against the dualistic tendencies of the school of thought associated with the Sutras. The Gita To a very brief characterization of the teaching of the Gita we must now turn. It had its place, as we have seen, as a mem¬ ber of the Prasthanatraya, or £ Canon 5 , of the Vedanta, and therefore must be considered in any survey of the development preparatory to Sankara’s teaching. It is more of a poem than a treatise, and its importance is not, strictly speaking, philo¬ sophical, but lies rather in the influence which it had upon popular thought, and in the expression which it gave to the theistic and slightly dualistic elements latent in the speculations of the Upanishads. As was suggested in the last paragraph, it does not seem to be essential to decide whether its dualism is preparatory to that of the Sutras or is itself strengthened by the teaching of the latter. Thibaut takes the former view and Prof. Das Gupta the latter. 1 But whatever may be the proper decision on this point, it can easily be seen that the composite character of such a work as the Gita would naturally give encouragement to dualistic tendencies. As regards the inter-relation of its elements, we may either take the view that the poem was a late Upanishad, somewhat similar in type to the §veiasvatara Upanishad , and containing the outlines of the generally monistic teaching of the Upani¬ shads and that this monism was then brought into relation with the teaching of the Bhagavata sect, whose worship centred in Krishna, regarded as an embodiment of Vishnu. Or the matter may be viewed from the other side, and, with Prof. Garbe, it may be said that the poem shows evidences of the transforma¬ tion of primitive trust in a warrior leader such as Krishna into faith in a personal supreme spirit. Krishna becomes identified 1 Cf. S. B. E. XXXIV, p. cxxvi, and Das Gupta, 422, and for further discussion of date, Farquhar, 91, and Urquhart, Pantheism and the Value of Life, 379. IN THE GlTA 45 with Vishnu or Vasudeva, the latter being either a popular designation of the former or the name of a deity already almost identified with him. But Vishnu (or Vasudeva) is also on the point of being identified with the impersonal non-qualitative Brahman—the subject of the more severely monistic doctrine of the Upanishads. Thus, from whatever direction we view the process of modification, Vishnu obtains the elevation which results from identification with the Absolute, and at the same time the Absolute is prevented from receding into these depths of negation and unapproachability which are suggested by some aspects of Upanishad teaching. The All-God becomes associ¬ ated with qualities which constitute him a definite object of worship, and from him 'the world-process emerges—as a real emanation and not simply as an illusive shadow-play. To a certain extent the tendency in the direction of realism and even dualism may be ascribed to the influence of the Sankhya philosophy. The writer of the Gita was not unaffected by the desire to adjust his teaching to the requirements of this philosophy, especially in its readiness to assign independent existence to matter, and many of his practical precepts owe much to the conception of external and resistless physical might. He does not of course go so far as consciously and definitely to admit the validity of this conception, but we cannot but see traces of pre-occupation with such a view, and the effect of it is indicated in the inclination towards a realistic view of the world. Practically, as Prof. Das Gupta points out, the ‘Bhagavadglta tried to mark out a middle path between the austere discipline of meditative abstraction, on the one hand, and the course of duties of sacrificial action ... in the life of a new type of Yogin on the other, who should combine in himself the best parts of the two paths, devote himself to his duties, and yet abstract himself from all selfish motives associated with desires’. 1 Thus on a rapid and conjunct view of the Prasthanat raya or ‘Canon’ we are left with an impression that no one tendency can claim absolute ascendancy, but that, if monism and a certain degree of negation seem to prevail in the Upanishads, in the other two members of the canon there are at least signs of a 1 Das Gupta, 227. 46 ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS dualistic tendency of sufficient strength to make it intelligible that in the minds of some a renewed emphasis on monistic principles would seem to be necessary. As we trace the develop¬ ment further, we find such an emphasis in Gaudapada and his Karikas. Gaudapada Gaudapada is a noteworthy figure in the tradition which San¬ kara inherited. There does not seem to be sufficient reason to doubt the authenticity of the name or to place the date of the work attributed to him so early as to render quite impossible his historical connexion with Sankara. The Gaudapada with whom we have to do is the reputed author of a poem known as the Mandukya Karika, and should not be identified with the earlier author of a commentary on Isvara Krishna’s Sankhya Karikas, as Max Muller seems to suggest. 1 Our Gaudapada was connected by direct links of historical anticipation with Sankara, and the latter speaks even of having come under the direct influence of Gaudapada. It would therefore probably be correct, if we accept the usual dating of Sankara (to be discussed later), to place Gaudapada about the end of the eighth century a.d. His work—the Mandukya Karika —is one of the earliest embodiments of the doctrine of strict monism. Sankara cor¬ dially welcomes him as a predecessor and declares that to him is due the credit of recovering and restating the absolutist creed which he holds to be the true teaching of the Veda. In rever¬ ential language Sankara thus refers to his preceptor: ‘That great guru ... on finding all the people sinking in the ocean made dreadful by the crocodiles of rebirth, out of kindness for all people, by churning the great ocean of the Veda by his churning rod of wisdom, recovered what lay deep in the heart of the Veda, and is hardly attainable even by the im¬ mortal gods.’ 3 It is acknowledged on all hands that Gaudapada was greatly influenced by Buddhistic teaching, and it is indeed possible— as alleged by some—that he may have been himself a Buddhist. Prof. Poussin says of him that it is impossible to read his verses 1 Muller, S. S. } 224. . '* Quoted by Das Gupta, 423. IN GAUDAPADA’S KARIKAS 47 ‘without being struck by the Buddhistic character of the leading ideas and of the wording itself. 1 He seems to have used the Buddhist doctrine of the Void’ as a key to the interpretation of the teaching of the Upanishads, and it has been suggested, as, e.g., by Prof. Das Gupta, 2 that he selected one of the smallest Upanishads—the Mandukya —and at the same time one that had much to say about dreams, as the basis of his Commentary, in order that he might not be drawn aside by the multiplicity of details in the larger Upanishads from his main purpose of concentrating attention on this truth of illusion. 3 It must not be supposed, however, that Gaudapada used this small Upani- shad simply as a peg on which to hang Buddhistic teaching. 1 To whatever extent others may differ from him in the interpre¬ tation of it, we must in fairness believe that he regarded Buddhistic doctrine as suggesting to him an interpretation which could actually be found in the Upanishad, and was, indeed, its fundamental truth. It is significant of Gaudapada’s attitude that the word may a, which was in previous literature of very rare occurrence, is to be found in no fewer than sixteen passages in his Karika, and one of the four chapters is entitled Vaitathya, or ‘unreality’. His view is that we may discuss, if we like, theories of creation and cosmogony, but it is of little importance which we adopt, for, after all, all plurality, and indeed all creation, is a dream, and the truth lies in the One. Cf. Mandukya Upanishad II. io, ‘Therefore this false notion arises from some cause due to ignorance, and so it is unreal, and would cease when instruc¬ tion is imparted by a Teacher. This is the saying of the wise, that “when One is known, the Two cease to exist”. The illusion is so extreme that it can hardly have that degree of actuality which demands destruction; having practically no reality, it does not stand in need of ‘burning’ or removal. We do not require spades and shovels to remove a morning mist; and when * ci.jf. JR. A. s., Vol. X, p. 134. 3 P. 429. 3 Cf. especially Mandukya U, I. 7, ‘others think that the creation is like unto a dream or an illusion.’ Madhva’s comment on this is that people of this class are ‘ignorant’. Prof. S. C. Vasu suggests also that it is ridiculous to think that the Almighty should revert to illusion. It is only, he argues, a hypnotist, who cannot actually produce an object, who is compelled to create an illusion. Cf. S. B. H. Mandukya, 12. 48 ANTICIPATIONS OF VEDANTIC IDEAS truth arises, the world-illusion disappears, as the morning mist fades away before the rising of the sun. The world of ordinary experience is to be placed in the same category as dreams. There are indeed many differences between the phenomena of dreams and those of waking reality, but they have in common the condition of ‘being seen’. Both of them are, in other words, the product of imagination. Further the subject or conceiver of these inner states is itself unreal, at least in its supposed distinction from the All.f Truth lies most of all in the Void, in the infinite of empty space (the akasa). Spaces enclosed in the jar or in the individual life, may appear to be separate, but when the jar is broken or the illusion of the jlva is dispelled, then follows complete merging in the whole of characterless being. No duality remains anywhere; all particu¬ larity is mere illusion and magic. The world of becoming is full of puzzling contradictions, and, in true Parmenidean fashion, Gaudapada holds that it can be understood only when it is completely denied./ The ordinary experiences of birth, life, and death are popular superstitions, and the sage who is worthy of the name will penetrate the illusion./The categories of causality, &c., cannot properly be used, for they immediately reveal insuperable contradictions and absurdities. If, e.g. you admit, with the Sankhyans, that cause and effect are inseparable, the logical result of such identification is that the effect will have to be regarded as unoriginated like the cause and the cause will be impermanent like the effect. So, he urges, let us by wisdom seek to penetrate the illusion. In and by consciousness is generated the illusion of both per- ceiver and perceived, and our consciousness is not separate from the eternal consciousness. Thus the power of illusion may be traced back to God Himself, unreality may be placed at the very heart of things, and everything except the one be dissolved in the conception of cosmic deception. The variety and forces of the world, and the life which we live within it, will all alike be emptied of meaning. Our life may be compared to the con¬ tinuous circle produced by a whirling firebrand, and in our life also by a metaphorical alatasanti (or extinction of the firebrand), we may discover that all ordinary experience is unreal as the circle of light produced by children at play in the gathering IN GAUDAPADA’S KARIKAS 49 twilight. Soon all will be dark, and in the darkness the truth lies hidden, and in the sense of unreality the real. 1 Negation could hardly go farther than this, and it was left for Sankara to take up the development of thought, and show how negation might reasonably go almost as far as this, and yet not lead to utter futility but form the way of approach to a reality positive in the very highest degree. 1 Cf. Prof. P. D. Shastri, Doctrine of Maya, 84. E Ill g Aft KARA AND RAMANUJA: THEIR LIVES, THEIR COMMENTARIES, AND THEIR TRADITIONAL PHILOSOPHICAL SIGNIFICANCE I T has been already pointed out that the peculiar character of the Sutras with which we are specially concerned has led to the general necessity of commentaries. Whilst other Sutras might possibly be understood without assistance, the case was altogether different with the two supreme Sutras (of which the Vedanta Sutras is one). Their mnemonic character and technical language made commentaries indispensable, and they could be made intelligible only if elucidated by those who were qualified to reproduce their original setting and proceed consistently from it. A recent Indian writer says, As for the Sutias, it is in theii nature to be easily elastic; and when unsupported by tradition, nothing indeed can be made out of them.’ 1 The commentators, of whom Sankara and Ramanuja are the chief, set themselves to restate the thoughts suggested or suggestible by the Sutras. The indefiniteness and vagueness of the Upanishads also provided an additional necessity for Commentaries. Seeing that the Sutras, although they purported to give the essence of the Upanishad teaching, had yet failed, by reason of their obscurity, to present this teaching in any authoritative form, it still remained open to, and, indeed, obligatory upon, succeeding scholars to establish what they regarded as the true doctrine of the sacred literary deposit. Their function, as they conceived it, was not to initiate new speculation, except perhaps in compara¬ tively insignificant details, but to make clear the exact meaning of the authorities whom they professed to revere. We have already referred to the esotericism of previous literature and to Deussen’s suggestion that this esotericism was deliberate. While we cannot subscribe altogether to the view that the esotericism was intentional, yet it is undoubted that such an attitude must have formed the background of thought, and it is exceedingly natural that the commentators should be influenced by the same spirit. This would almost inevitably 1 Aiyar, 73. LIFE AND TEACHING OF SANKARA 51 express itself in the endeavour to enhance the value of their esoteric possession. They would proceed to do this by elaborat¬ ing it as much as possible, by developing suggestions into systems and intuitions into arguments, so that the initiates might feel that they had not been led on by false hopes, but had really been made to share in an inheritance of the greatest significance. And seeing that the commentators had bestowed so much labour upon it, they might quite justifiably feel that they were conferring a boon which was very much worth giving. The greater the elaboration the greater the value of what they had to impart. But we must not think of them as influenced exclusively by an esoteric spirit. While cherishing this and making as much of it as possible, they at the same time wished to give interpretations which would be more widely intelligible and acceptable. For their own reputation they would wish to do this; and motives also of a higher and benevolent character would enter in. ^While Sankara always preserved an esoteric kernel of his thought, which he declared to be only for the few, yet he was frequently also animated by a genuinely missionary spirit, under the influence of which he felt himself called upon to dilute his thought for the benefit of the multitude. It should be noted that a Bhashya—the name often given to a commentary—is not properly a commentary in the usually accepted sense of the word. Its primary aim is not to elucidate a text (although it may do this with considerable thoroughness), but rather to construct a philosophy on the basis of the authori¬ tative text selected. A comparison may again be made with the procedure in Indian music according to which the rag, or fixed form, while dominating any new composition, at the same time permits of very considerable variation. Life of Sankara Sankara is the earliest of the commentators on the Sutras whose work is extant, and he is still regarded as the most important in the whole succession. He has been described in glowing terms as ‘the greatest intellect of the world’ and ‘the most towering personality of Hinduism in its renaissance period’. 1 He is said to have been born at Kaladi in North 1 Cf. Pal, 1 and 16. E 2 5 2 3 ANKARA AND RAMANUJA Travancore about the year a.d. 788. There is considerable unanimity about the year of his birth, but whether he died at the comparatively early age of thirty-two, or lived to a good old age, perhaps until about the year 850, seems to be a matter of great uncertainty. To those who argue that 820 was the date of his death the reply is made , that this was merely the date of his final renunciation of all ties which bound him to ordinary life; and, generally speaking, biographers seem to be undecided whether the greater honour will accrue to Sankara if he is regarded as an example of youthful precocity or found to be a depositary of the garnered wisdom of a lengthy life. His biographers are numerous, but it cannot be said that they supply us with a very trustworthy record. Indeed some of them frankly disavow any direct dependence on historical fact. ‘What have we to do with the minor incidents of Sankara’s life?’ says Mr. D. N. Pal. 1 ‘We have his philosophy, we have his religion, we have his personality, we have his Ethics. All Hindus . . . breathe in Sankara’s spirit.’ The poverty of biographical material may indeed be taken as simply an illustration of the self-effacing spirit of all India’s great religious teachers; it is but fit ting that their outer life should be a blank and that the details of it should not remain in the memory of man. Consequently it is argued that, if there are not facts available by the interpreta¬ tion of which we may arrive at an appreciation of the spirit of a man, it is quite permissible, after having obtained from his teaching some indication of his character, to construct a body of ‘facts’ suitable for expressing the spirit of this character. We may argue that ‘if this is not true, then something like it is true’, or we may apply the very elastic measurement which seems to be suggested by Mr. Pal in such words as ‘It is a very probable story, and assuredly a true story’. 2 The way is thus opened for the expression of enthusiastic admiration under the guise of the forms of biography. It must not, however, be thought that Indian writers are all liable to this tendency. Mr. C. N. Krishnaswami Aiyar, e.g., takes up a much more critical attitude, and speaks very severely of ‘the misguided enthusiasm of later admirers from whom every great person has reason to pray to be saved’. 1 Pal, 96. a lb. 57- LIFE AND TEACHING OF SANKARA S3 But it would on the whole be true to say that in considering the lives of Sankara we have for the most part to deal with facts which are under the governance of ideas, or with facts which have burst through the limitations of history and are on the way to becoming transparent expressions of spiritual truths. And, after all, there is not much reason to complain, for there is abundant justification in the frequent contention of Indian biographers that Sankara's teaching is of much more importance than his life, and we need not be too anxious to distinguish rigidly between history and drama, or be too critical of attempts to give this teaching an appropriate setting in concrete circumstance if this setting helps us to understand the teaching more adequately. Even if, on occasion, the alleged facts are merely the product of ‘misguided enthusiasm', the statement of them is useful as a proof of the existence of the enthusiasm and an indication of its extent, and we may safe¬ guard ourselves by valuing the enthusiasm according to our estimate of the intrinsic excellence of the teaching rather than on the basis of the facts which are supposed to have evoked it. With this proviso—that the enthusiasm should be related to the ideas rather than to the facts’—we may proceed to give a brief account of the details of his life which are fairly generally agreed upon. Considerable mystery surrounds his birth, and an instance of retrospective narrative, wise after the event, is immediately forthcoming in the story that Sankara's mother, having been offered the choice of having a number of dunces or only one short-lived but clever son, decided in favour of the latter. His steadfastness of purpose, even in his early years, is indicated by the stress which his biographers lay upon the degree of family opposition which he had to overcome in order to carry out his desire of becoming a sannydsi. One event of his early life is well authenticated and of con¬ siderable importance. His search for a Guru led him to become a pupil of Govinda, who, as we have already seen, was himself a pupil of Gaudapada. This shows that Sankara was at the beginning of his career brought under the influence of the rigorously monistic doctrine which was the prevailing doctrine of Gaudapada's Karikds; and here there is also indicated a channel of Buddhistic influence. An entirely apocryphal story, 54 Sankara and rAmanuja chronologically of course impossible, tells how, after Sankara had settled at Benares, he was visited by Vyasa, the reputed author of the Vedanta-sutras , and had many long and learned conversations with him. This story might be taken as indicating allegorically Sankara’s early interest in the meaning of the Sutras , and might also suggest the beginning of controversy as to whether he was properly interpreting them, the visit of Vyasa being cited of course in order to show that Sankara had oppor¬ tunities of first-hand knowledge such as almost made mistake impossible. Of more importance are his disputations with Mandana Misra, the favourite pupil of Kumarila Bhatta, who was famous as a reactionary from Buddhism, and a staunch defender of the ritual and sacrificial practices which had been handed down from Vedic times—the way of works, or the karma-marga. In Sankara’s victorious disputation with Man¬ dana we have a presentation of the former’s fundamental preference for the way of knowledge over the way of works. At the same time the contrast between the vigorous persecution which Mandana, as well as his predecessor Kumarila Bhatta, directed against the Buddhists, and the more tolerant attitude of Sankara towards his vanquished opponents is an expression of Sankara’s catholicity, and also a parallel in the practical sphere to that theoretical method which allowed him unconcernedly to place side by side esoteric and exoteric truth and permit con¬ tinued adherence to the latter until such time as the former should prevail. In passing, also, we may allude to the pathetic but beautiful story of Sankara’s interview with his dying mother. She had asked him to discourse on matters which would bring peace to her soul, but he began to expound the abstruse doctrines of his philosophy. On finding that these gave her no comfort, he fell back upon hymns of devotion which he himself had composed in honour of Siva. The inclusion of this story—whatever its historicity—indicates an impression in the minds of his biographers that Sankara’s doctrines were too abstruse for the ordinary mind and needed to be accompanied by some accommodation to the simpler understanding. Also the story of his interview with one of the Kapalikas (or skull-men), who asked Sankara for the gift of his head as a sacrifice to Kali, urging that, according to the principles of the LIFE AND TEACHING OF SANKARA 55 Advaita philosophy, Sankara ought to be completely indifferent to the loss of such an appurtenance of individuality, reads almost like a satire designed to bring out the unpractical nature of Sankara’s teaching. Sankara spent several years at Benares, and it was probably there that he made a beginning with the chief works with which his name is associated. But his life was essentially that of a peripatetic philosopher, and tradition has it that he travelled all over India. He seems to have had considerable gifts of organization, and several Mutts, or houses of monastic learning, which continue to this day, owe their origin to him. He is said to have ended his life at Kedarnath, in the far north of India, but whether his death took place in 820 or thirty years later is still a matter of uncertainty. Provisioned summary of Sankara s teaching. We may give here a preliminary indication of the main points in Sankara’s doctrine. By representative Indian writers San¬ kara is described as a ‘rigorous monist ’, 1 and perhaps such a' phrase gives us most concisely the key-note of his teaching. He asserts"one reairtyi'affd only oniTfor there is no such things pluHIiTy or differehce anywhere, and, therefore, no beginning anTno ending, nothing but that nearest experience which comes toeach one of us, the consciousness of the self, intell igent just SeSmsTitir’ iAiWhial 7lf w ecan merge all things in our consciousness, and merge ourselves as individuals in the universal consciousness, we shall reach the goal of all our striving, the solution of all our difficulties. If we can negate the world we sha ll fin d that the world is well lost, for there is really _n ^ to l ose, n(^m^but^theJjl^srva 4 ^B&^.f^Sg^lif^^j:^^.^V , th e~fundamental. self-luminous Being. ' And yet even in the shortest sumfnary, it is necessary to express the doubt whether the mood which lies behind this attitude is really so negative as might at first sight appear. Can we go so far as to call it altogether negative? May it not be rather that simpler but more fundamental feeling of the stupen¬ dousness of the universe which overwhelms mankind at the first 1 Cf. Kirtikar , 2. 56 Sankara and rAmanuja dawning of the religious consciousness? The burden of aware¬ ness seems almost too great for us to bear, and would crush us were not some means found of lessening its weight. And may not the human mind under such conditions find refuge in the thought that much of the burden is unreal—in fact that it is all unreal, except in so far as we find ourselves again in it and dis¬ cover that the seeming oppression is but the insistence upon us of the universal in which we live and move and have our being? Sankara’s thought may be followed along the usual lines made familiar to us by idealist philosophy. Being is essentially relative to thought. No object can exist except as known—'Where there is no knowledge, there is no knowable. 51 And carrying forward with him the ideal of knowledge suggested even in the days of Vedic sacrifice in India—the ideal of the merging of the knower and the known, of the mystic communion of subject and object following upon the destruction of the separateness of the wor¬ shipper and the worshipped—Sankara proceeds to sublate all the distinctions which divide the subject and the object, and the variety of particular objects from each other. Space, time, causality, and other categories both definite and vague, even the thought of difference itself, are all swept out of the way until the soul is left only with the sense of the unity of individual experience. And the differences disappear in pure being with which consciousness also is found to be at one. Our consciousness is not really individual, for it is beginning¬ less, and no individual can be without a beginning. It has more¬ over no lurking plurality within itself, no distinction of a knower behind his knowledge which may form the basis of a quasi¬ material separateness. Sankara warns us against attributing objective qualities to the subject, by which warning he means that we should not attempt to view the self in an external way, as if it were merely an ordinary object, popularity and particu- larly conceived. Consciousness is not possessed by some entity beyond consciousness, but is pure consciousness, ultimate being, transparent through and through. There can be no distinction between the individual and the universal, any more than between the individual subject and the object known. Pure undifferenced unity is all that can be established. 1 Gf. Sankara’s Commentary on Prasna XJ. VI. 2. LIFE AND TEACHING OF SANKARA 57 But whence then came the world with all the details of our ordinary experience? We cannot avoid its recognition, but we should regard it as only phenomenal, as having merely vyava- harika or practical existence. Even this amount of existence is due to ignorance, and not to our ignorance only but to a cosmic ignorance This cosmic ignorance when combined with power becomes a principle of illusion or Maya. This cosmic, phan¬ tasm-creating energy is beginningless,_ and, although thejjhi- mate Being or Brahman is without qualities or without plurality, somehow orbther it becomes attaclied to him. It is both sat and asat, the first as not being due only to our invention, and the second as being, after all, only phenomenal. It is an eternal power producing unreal appearances. ... . It is difficult to unfold all that is contained in this double mode of conceiving the principle as at once real and umeal. But it might be a step forward in interpretation to say that the principle is an absolute expression of the idea of the mex- plicable—according to Prof. Radhakrishnan, a statement of a metaphysical position which might thus be described: As for the metaphysical ramifications which also exist, the non-dualist says, well, they are there, and there is an end of it. We do not know and cannot know why. It is all a contradiction and yet it is actual.’ 1 Now, from the point of view of a completely rounded philosophy, the idea of the inexplicable carries with it a slightly depreciatory significance, and perhaps this idea of subjective disapproval is intended to be conveyed in some of the interpretations of the term Maya, which, notwithstanding many rehabilitations, never quite detaches itself from the idea of illusion, deepening occasionally into the ideas of delusion and deception. In any case it tends always to suggest something of the idea of a lower reality, what should not he from the point of view of true knowledge. At the same time this conception of Maya does afford us some relief from the burden of the inex¬ plicable, just as on awaking from a troublesome and perplexing dream we are comforted by discovering that it is nothing but a dream. In association with the power of Maya , Brahman becomes Isvara, the Absolute with qualities, the Creator, the Preserver, l Radhakrishnan, 1 .35. S 8 Sankara and rAmAnuja and Destroyer of the world. In this way the phenomenal world may, in contradiction to the Buddhists, be provisionally accepted, and the variety of nature, as well as the existence of individual souls may be to a certain extent explained, all materialistic and purely naturalistic theories being, as a conse¬ quence, ruled out of court. But yet, however perfect the sys¬ tematization may be, it has to be confessed in the end that the universe thus constructed is not real in the fullest sense, and our salvation will consist in attaining this knowledge. Such know¬ ledge will not be an active force destroying error, but simply a recognition that the content of error does not exist. Our liberation will proceed by various stages, as we gradually get rid of the limiting adjuncts or ‘sheaths’ of our personality. We rise from the life of pure impulse to that of ritual observance, which will lead us by the ‘way of the fathers’—th epitriyana — to an existence of considerable, though temporary, enjoyment. The next stage is marked by a worship of the highest qualitative Brahman, and ‘by way of the gods’—the Devayana —will bring us to the divine regions where we shall live in communion with this Brahman of qualities. But when this qualitative Brahman is merged in the Brahman without qualities, we ourselves may share in this identification, and reach, or rather discover, a state in which we are united with the Para-Brahman, without the slightest difference remaining. Life and Teaching of Ramanuja After this purely provisional account of the Advaitavada of Sankara we may turn to a short treatment of the life and teaching of Ramanuja, in order that we may set the two great teachers in relation to each other, and be in a position to decide which of them we ought chiefly to follow in our further exposition of the Vedanta. That some sort of choice has to be made between them will be evident from the vigorous way in which Ramanuja himself states his opposition to the doctrines of Sankara. Adverse judgement could hardly be more uncompromisingly expressed than in the following passage: ‘This entire theory rests on a fictitious foundation of altogether hollow and vicious arguments, incapable of being stated in definite logical alterna¬ tives, and devised by men who are destitute of those particular LIFE AND TEACHING OF RAMANUJA 59 qualities which cause individuals to be chosen by the Supreme Person revealed in the Upanishads ; whose intellects aie dark¬ ened by the impression of beginningless evil; and who thus have no insight into the meaning of words and sentences, into the real purport conveyed by them, and into the procedure of sound argumentation, with all its methods depending on per¬ ception and other instruments of right knowledge. The theory therefore must needs be rejected by all those who, through texts, perception, and the other means of knowledge assisted by sound reasoning—have an insight into the true nature of things.’ 1 This quotation not only indicates vehemence of oppo¬ sition, but is also a guide to the points upon which criticism was to be specially directed. It shows, amongst other things, that Ramanuja disapproved of the idea of a beginningless power of Maya and did not share the distrust of human faculties therein implied; and also that, in his opinion, Sankara was not a reliable interpreter of the Upanishads, which pointed to the existence rather of a Supreme Person than of a characterless Absolute. 3 Ramanuja is important both on his own account and on account of the tradition which he represents. His Commentary is the next oldest to that of Sankara, and is itself a brilliant piece of exposition and criticism, described by a recent competent writer as one of the most influential works that India has produced. 3 And the same writer seems disposed to regard him, in relation to Sankara, as a typical representative of one of the fundamental metaphysical tendencies in the history of human thought: ‘For two Magnitudes of the highest rank struggle here with each other in Sankara and Ramanuja, who are only their representatives. The almost altogether mysterious and over¬ whelming, world-destroying, ultimately irrational, inconceiv¬ able, undefinable Absolute Unity is in conflict with the Lord, the feeling, willing, personal, rational, loving, and beloved God of the heart and conscience.’ 4 1 Cf. S. B. E. XLVIII. 8. . . .. ■ 2 The vigour of language in the passage just cited almost justifies the comment of Prof. Otto, ‘And now begins the struggle of proposition against proposition, assertion against assertion—a struggle in the truest sense, breast to breast, and knee to knee, a struggle of the utmost intensity, without pause to draw breath or take, until limb by limb the opponent is overcome and crushed to the earth* (Otto, Siddhanta des Ramanuja , 2). 3 Cf. Otto, op, dt., p. 1. 4 Op-, dt.y p. 2, 60 Sankara and ramanuja From the point of view of history rather than of metaphysics, Ramanuja might be described as one who has carried further the more purely theistic teaching of the Vedanta Sutras. He was not at all distressed by the slightly dualistic and realistic tendency which had set in before the time of Sankara, and from which the latter represented a reaction. Rather was he inclined to welcome such a tendency. He would have ranged himself alongside of Kumarila Bhatta in opposition to the Buddhists, and, while he would also have sympathized with much of the anti-ritualistic fervour which placed Sankara in opposition to Kumarila Bhatta, he was by no means disposed to go all the way with Sankara in the direction of abstraction. He had much more regard for the ordinary religious needs of humanity, and was unwilling to patronize the populace by allowing them graciously to occupy a lower station while a higher one was reserved for the true philosopher. He held that religious satis¬ faction and metaphysical validity might coincide, and that the air of the highest heights to which the philosopher might aspire was not too rarified for common men to breathe. If the common man still had to be selected from a somewhat restricted class, this disability might be put down to traditional caste-necessity and not to intrinsic intellectual or spiritual inferiority. Ramanuja’s period was the end of the eleventh century and the beginning of the twelfth. He was born at Sri-perumbudur, near Madras, and, after a youth of extraordinary precocity, he became the Acharya, or spiritual leader connected with the temple at Srirangam, near Trichinopoly, and at the same time occupied the position of Acharya of the Sri-Vaishnava sect, the greatest of all the Vaishnava sects. It is said that his domestic life was not particularly happy, and he suffered much from sectarian persecution. He seems from the first to have adopted a more liberal attitude towards non-Brahman castes than did some of his predecessors. He indeed restricted the reading of the Vedas to the ‘twice-born’, but he was willing to communi¬ cate his religious teaching even to Sudras and outcastes. The story is told of him that with great difficulty he persuaded a certain guru to unlock for him the secrets of the esoteric mysteries, under promise that these secrets would not be pub¬ lished except to a worthy disciple who had been properly tested. LIFE AND TEACHING OF RAMANUJA 61 Ramanuja, however, found that the doctrines were so impor¬ tant and so vital for salvation, that for the sake of the general good he preferred himself to become a castaway if by any means —even by the breaking of a promise—he could save some. When the Guru in the vehemence of wrath threatened him with eternal punishment hereafter, Ramanuja replied that he would gladly suffer hell himself if he could bring a message of salvation to the suffering people. He represented to a considerable extent the tendency or thought manifested in the Puranas. He was an adherent further of the Vaishnava religion in which great stress was laid on the bhakti attitude to the divine. Within the confines of this sect Ramanuja entered into a kind of apostolical succession. Amongst its leaders at an earlier period was a special group of devotees called Alvars, who were renowned for their religious hymns and honoured as saints almost on the threshold of divinity. They laid special stress on the central tenet of bhakti , and, while holding no official place in the sect, were exceedingly influential by reason of the nobility and_purity of their lives. These were succeeded by a group called Acharyas, regarded as perhaps less fully inspired, but still greatly venerated. They exercised a considerable amount of authority over the sect, and performed certain priestly functions. Of these Ramanuja was said to be the fifth in succession. But, notwithstanding the strength of traditional influence, Ramanuja’s acceptance of the views he ultimately held was the result of conscious choice following upon controversy, and was not merely mechanical. At Conjeeveram he studied for some time under Yadavaprakasa, a teacher of the school of Sankara, and Ramanuja’s adherence to a modified form of monism was the result of repeated study of the pure monism of his guru. Much travelling in search of instruction had the effect of strengthening him in his views, and finally he felt himself qualified to succeed Alavandar, his immediate predecessor in the list of Acharyas—at the famous temple of Srirangam. This place continued to be his head-quarters, except when driven into exile by reason of Saiva persecution, and during one long journey which he undertook for the spreading of his doctrines. His long life came to an end in 1137. 6 z ^ANKARA AND RAMANUJA By his energy he consolidated the sect to which he belonged and left a powerful organization behind him. But his theoretical consolidation was of much greater importance than his institu¬ tional, for in his Srlbhashya he gave to his sect a supporting philosophy, and at the same time, seeing that he commented on such important documents as the Vedanta Sutras , traced that philosophy back to the traditional Vedanta sources. The twin principles of bhakti and vidya which Ramanuja followed strikingly indicate his close connexion both with the popular polytheistic and theistic religion on the one hand and also with central philosophical tendencies on the other. These principles, moreover, interact with each other in his system to their mutual advantage. The intensely emotional fervour associated with bhakti, as, e.g., in the Bhagavata Purana, was never adopted by Ramanuja, and his bhakti is of a much more moderate type. On the other hand the coldly philosophical meditations of thinkers such as Sankara are humanized and diverted from the abstract to the concrete. With such a tradition and in such an environment it was to be expected that Ramanuja would not be able to approve of Sankara’s doctrine of two orders of knowledge which compelled the seeker to go beyond a Divine Being who could attract the human heart and fill it with devotion, and search for an abstract unqualified Absolute. For Ramanuja there was not a higher and a lower Brahman, but the so-called ‘lower’ Brahman was himself the ultimate, compact of auspicious qualities. The favourite assertion of the monists that here there ‘was no diversity’ was simply meant, according to Ramanuja, to imply the unification of the attributes (which were incapable of ulti¬ mately detached existence) and the denial of any source of power other than Brahman. Creation is real and not a merely illusory activity. To three entities reality must always be allowed—to God, the individual souls, and non-intelligent matter. To God two stages of existence must be assigned. In the pralaya state of absolute quiescence souls and matter exist in Him in subtle form. At creation, again, they come forth into visible expression, and creation is the result of a positive volitional effort on the part of Brahman, who pervades the universe in which he expresses himself and in relation to whom LIFE AND TEACHING OF RAMANUJA 63 all living creatures exist as modes (prakara ). The individual soul is not essentially one with Brahman in the sense that it has no present freedom and is bound eventually to lose its individua¬ lity. Rather does it become one with Brahman merely in the sense of acquiring the divine qualities, and its destiny, when it is released, through steady devotion and contemplation and by the gift of the grace of God, from the trammels of transmigra¬ tion, is to enjoy communion in paradise with the personal Lord of all. The general character of Ramanuja’s conception of God was such that it was possible for him, without intellectual con¬ tradiction, to identify Brahman with Vishnu, the God of the Vaishnavas, and at the same time to claim that the worship of Vishnu was a direct fulfilment of the teaching of the Vedanta textsj and the religious counterpart of the only tenable philo¬ sophical position. Ramanuja’s work had considerable influence upon subsequent religious development and gave to the faith of the Vaishnavas a stability and dignity which it did not previously possess. 1 Sankara’s philosophy is known as Advaita (non-dualism), and Ramanuja’s as Visishtadvaita (modified non-dualism), and it will be obvious from the short account we have given of the tenets of the two philosophers that the qualifying adjective indicates a very vital difference. That the second of the pro¬ tagonists was himself vividly conscious of the difference is evident from the quotation we have already given from Rama¬ nuja’s own polemical writings. The intensity of opposition has not diminished in the course of the centuries, as is indicated by a saying recently attributed to a leader of one of the schools of thought in southern India, which is dominated by the Visisht¬ advaita doctrine He is represented as declaring that he had rather see all India abandoning Hinduism altogether than that ‘it should fall a prey to the Vedanta of Sankara’. 2 It will there¬ fore be readily understood how difficult it is in any exposition of the Vedanta to include as equally important data the teach¬ ings of both Sankara and Ramanuja. As Max Muller says, ‘It must be admitted that in India, instead of one Vedanta philo- 1 We may note especially his influence on the doctrines of the Satwata school, as these are set forth by Prof. Bhagavat Kumar Shastri in his book upon The Bhakti Cult in Ancient India. Cf. pp. 173 ff. ^Quoted in Frazer’s Indian Thought } 72. 64 Sankara and rAmanuja sophy, we have really two, springing from the same root but extending its branches in two very different directions, that of Sankara being kept for unflinching reasoners who, supported by an unwavering faith in Monism, do not shrink from any of its consequences, . . . another, that of Ramanuja, trying hard to reconcile their Monism with the demands of the human heart that required, and always will require, a personal God, as the last cause of all that is, and an eternal soul that yearns for an approach to or a reunion with that Being. 51 It is therefore necessary to inquire which of the two philo¬ sophers is accepted as the typical Vedantist by Indian thinkers, and to what extent the popular verdict reflects a recognition of continuity between the favoured teaching on the one hand and the teaching of the Upanishads and the Vedanta Sutras on the other. If we can prove that one of the two rival commentators is clearly outstanding, the simplest procedure in our subsequent exposition will be to adopt as a basis the teaching accepted by the majority, and use the other as a starting-point for lines of criticism. There can be little doubt that pre-eminence must be assigned to Sankara. So far as counting of heads goes, it has been estimated even by a follower of Ramanuja that out of the total number of Vedantins 75 per cent, are adherents of Sankara, and only 15 per cent, of Ramanuja, while the remaining 10 per cent, may be distributed amongst minor sects also laying claim to the name of Vedantins. And that this popularity is not merely accidental, but is based upon and justified by a considered estimate of the significance of Sankara’s teaching, is evidenced by the opinion of leading scholars, even down to the present day. In their opinion the triumph of Vedantic ideas is due fundamentally to the work of Sankara. Tt was given to San¬ kara 5 , says Mr. C. N. Krishnaswami Aiyar, ‘to make Vedanta the basis of every religious sect that India has known, so as to satisfy the needs of men of all shades of intelligence and bias. 5 z And Mr. D. N. Pal, after citing a long list of appreciations of Vedantism to be found in the writings of European scholars, exclaims, ‘All this is due to Sankara. Without his master mind, this grand thing remained inconceivable. 5 3 Mr. P. N. Sen 1 Muller, S. S. 192. 2 Aiyar, 9. 3 Pal, 141* THE TEACHING OF SANKARA 65 holds that 'the philosophy of Sankara has now been unalterably identified with the Vedanta philosophy’. 1 Prof. S. N. Das Gupta writes in much the same strain, 'Whenever we speak of the Vedanta philosophy, we mean the philosophy that was expounded by Sankara,’ 2 and he claims also that the popularity of the philosophy is based on the intrinsic merit of 'the subtle and deep ideas it contains’. Dr. Thibaut takes the £ankara-bha~ shya to represent the orthodox side of Brahmanical theology and describes the doctrine advocated by Sankara as 'the most im¬ portant and interesting which has arisen on Indian soil; neither those forms of the Vedanta which diverge from the view repre¬ sented by Sankara nor any of the non-Vedantic systems can be compared with the so-called orthodox Vedanta in boldness, depth, and subtlety of speculation’. 3 Having established the centrality of Sankara himself in popu¬ lar and scholarly estimation, it now remains for us to ask whether he can serve himself heir to the fundamental ideas of his authorities, i.e. whether he can by right of succession be called orthodox. To what extent is he a reliable interpreter of the Upanishads and of the Sutras} Although both he and Ramanuja represent philosophical tendencies divergent alike from the Upanishads and the Sutras, and although—to borrow a metaphor from Max Muller—they both are citizens of philo¬ sophical colonies which have detached themselves to some extent from the mother-country, yet on the whole neither of them is so individualistic as to neglect the obvious strengthening of their respective positions which would come from a properly established connexion with the ancient authorities. They shared the universally accepted view that no system could be regarded as having sufficient standing if it could be shown to be in opposition to the tradition of ancient thought. It has already been shown, however, that we cannot assert any simple identifi¬ cation between the doctrines of the Upanishads and of the Sutras , and therefore we cannot expect that the attitude of Sankara and Ramanuja, whether divergent from each other or not, will be exactly the same in regard to the Sutras as in regard to the Upanishads. It may turn out that Sankara is the more 3 Das Gupta, I. 429. 3 S. B. E. XXXIV, p. xiv. F . 1 Sen, 5. 66 SANKARA AND RAMANUJA faithful interpreter of the Upanishads and Ramanuja of the Sutras , or vice versa. There are one or two a priori considerations which may throw some light upon the problem. Sankara, e.g., is disposed to treat the Sutras as of much less importance than the Upanishads. He assigns, as we have seen, to the former merely ‘the purpose of stringing together the flowers of the Vedanta passages’. 1 Consequently, if any conflict should arise between the Sutras and the Upanishads, Sankara will feel bound to accept the teaching of the latter rather than of the former, and will, on the other hand, feel more at liberty to transform the primary mean¬ ing of the Sutras. IVforeover, Sankara took a much stricter view than Ramanuja of the authority of the Upanishads. His attitude is predominantly one of submission leaving little room for free¬ dom. In his comment on I. r. 2 he indeed allows that, while supreme reverence is to be paid to the Vedanta texts, yet the knowledge derived from them may be supplemented by in¬ tuition which ‘may be had recourse to according to the occa¬ sion’., Inference also may be regarded as ‘an instrument of right knowledge in so far as it does not contradict the Vedanta texts’. But in reference to I. r. 11 he takes up the more uncom¬ promising position that ‘Reasoning which disregards the holy texts and rests on individual opinion only, has no proper founda¬ tion. . . . The true nature of the cause of the world cannot. . . even be thought of without the help of the holy texts.’ We shall return a little later to Sankara’s general conception of the place of authority, but in the meantime it may be noted that in relation especially to the Upanishads his attitude will lead us to expect an exceedingly careful rendering of what he takps to be their meaning. On the other hand, we may note that Ramanuja adopts a much freer attitude to the Upanishads, and lays down the general principle that, when perception and Scripture come into conflict, Scripture is not necessarily to be regarded as the more authoritative. 2 As a consequence of this we may ve^y naturally form the expectation that in any cases of variance between the Upanishads and the Sutras, Ramanuja will feel more at liberty to follow the plain meaning of the Sutras. 1 Cf. Commentary on Sutra I. r. 2, S. B.E. XXXIV. 17. * Cf. S.B.E. XLVIII. 73. THE TEACHING OF SANKARA 67 Another a priori consideration has reference to the distribu¬ tion of the contents of the Sutras . By far the larger portion of them deals with topics which, according to Sankara’s principles, are of secondary importance. He will therefore be compelled to concentrate his attention upon what in respect of bulk is a minor portion, and, contrariwise, will be disposed to treat the major portion with considerable freedom and subject it to a method of interpretation which will detract from the importance it might have had on a plain rendering. He will have to expend a good deal of effort in order to extract from it a secondary meaning more in accordance with the import of the minor portion. It is, of course, possible that this secondary meaning will be the essential meaning, but the probabilities are the other way, and a priori we shall be disposed to attribute the greater accuracy to the simpler interpretation. The right to adopt an esoteric point of view must always be somewhat reluctantly conceded unless on other grounds it can be shown that the. Scriptures in question were intended to have a double meaning. The question of the affiliation of Sankara’s doctrine to the Sutras and the Upanishads respectively cannot, however, be decided on a priori grounds merely, but must depend for settle¬ ment on an investigation of the sources of some of Sankara’s leading doctrines. Dr. Thibaut has made an elaborate study of this question, and has selected as points for discussion the problems of two orders of knowledge, the distinction between a higher and a lower Brahman, the doctrine of Maya, and the relation of the individual souls to Brahman. 1 As our main purpose is expository rather than historical, a brief discussion of Sankara’s relations to the Sutras and the Upanishads as revealed in his treatment of these topics is all that is necessary here. We have seen that the distinction between ordinary and real knowledge is at the basis of much of Sankara’s teaching. The assumption is that statements maybe true from the vyavaharika or ordinary point of view, but not true from the pafamarthika or transcendental point of view. If this distinction is recognized 1 The same topics, though not in the same order, have been discussed at •considerable length in the present writer’s Pantheism and the Value of Life, 193-230. 68 SANKARA AND RAMlNUJA as fundamental in the Sutra teaching, we should naturally expect that only he would be regarded as having attained the highest stage of emancipation who had also attained to the highest knowledge. But, as a matter of fact, in the fourth division of the Sutras, a description is given at considerable length of one who knows Brahman, and yet this description is declared by Sankara to apply to one who only has the lower knowledge, and therefore cannot have risen to the level of the highest attainment possible. If, however, the Sutras had agreed with his view, it is difficult to understand how they could have placed such a description in such a setting where we should naturally have expected a reference to the highest conceivable state. The Isa Ufianishad I. 9 may seem to be a passage favour¬ able to Sankara’s view. Here it is said that ‘those who delight in knowledge enter, as it were, into greater darkness , and Sankara interprets it as indicating a depreciation of those who possess only the lower knowledge. But its true significance seems to be that it gives a decision on the point that when a choice has to be made between knowledge and works, the alter¬ native of knowledge alone is more dangerous than the alternative of works alone. About all that can be said in reference to Upanishad support of Sankara’s general distinction is that it affords a convenient method of arranging the different strata in their teaching and of dealing with higher and lower material. It is also difficult to prove that support can be found in the Sutras for the negative procedure which results in the identifi¬ cation of the individual soul with Brahman. Sankara indeed argues that individuality is entirely due to nescience, and that the ‘joining’ which is spoken of in Sutras 1 .1.19 can mean only identity and nothing else. It is, however, to be noticed that this interpretation is so far from being regarded as the only possible one, that Ramanuja, in reference to the same passage, makes the vigorous comment that ‘To say that any one is identical with that by which he obtains bliss, would be madness indeed’. 1 A passage having great significance for this question is to be found in Sutras II. 3.43, ‘The soul is a part of the Lord, on account of the declaration of difference.’ In order to bring this into agreement with his system, Sankara has to insert the * Cf. 5 . B. E. XLVIII. 236. THE TEACHING OF SANKARA 69 qualification, ‘a part, as it were? whereas Ramanuja can take the statement far more simply. Moreover, a slightly earlier Sutra of the same Pada 1 speaks of the soul as an ‘agent*, thus seeming to convey an impression of individuality. It would not be difficult, however, to show that the Upanishads give far greate r support than the Sutras to Sankara’s denial of in dividualit y. TTc^^aushliaki Upamshad maintenance of individuality, but such passages as Brihaddranyaka Upani- shad I. 4. 19, ‘From death to death goes he who sees plurality anywhere/ tell strongly in the opposite direction. Still more convincing is the consideration that the prevailing tendency of the Upanishads is in the direction of regarding the association of Brahman with plurality simply as a concession to the weakness of the empirical consciousness.'and of insisting that theJinal state is one of complete identifica tion of the individual soul w ith Bralimam The situation is very much the same in regard to Sankara’s distinction between the sagunam and nirgunam Brahman. This distinction does not seem to be supported by the Sutras . They persist in ascribing one quality after another to Brahman, and they put the inquiry into Brahman as ‘an ocean of auspicious qualities ’ in the very forefront of their endeavour. This, to say the least of it, would be a slightly curious and futile proceeding, if the Sutrakara indeed considered that the Brahman of qualities was not the highest from his point of view, even though it might not be the highest in the sense of the word ‘highest’ accepted by Sankara. But Sankara argues that, though it must be admitted that there are passages in the Upanishads which might very naturally be construed as referring to a qualitative Brahman, yet these very passages are contradicted by passages which come later; and, as a contradiction must always follow that which is contradicted, these later passages must be taken as more authoritative than the earlier. A criterion based upon the order of the passages is, however, of doubtful validity, and, in any case, if rigorously applied, the criterion would not always tell in favour of Sankara.3 At the same time Sankara is in the main justified in regard to the Upanishads. Although they do not 1 II. 3. 33. 2 Cf. especially II. 15. 3 Cf. the present writer’s Pantheism and the Value of Life, p. 198. 70 Sankara and ramanuja make any formal and explicit distinction between the qualitative and non-qualitative Brahman, yet their general tendency is in a negative direction and towards a Brahman of abstract charac¬ ter, in regard to which they can make use of only the vaguest predicates or of none at all. On the whole it would be correct to say that they show a distrust of any categories drawn from ordinary experience. In regard to the relation of God to the world, we have to ask whether the Sutras support Sankara’s view of Maya as a purely negative illusion. This question is bound up with the one we have just been considering, as, if a qualitative Brahman is to be regarded as the ultimate object of belief in the Sutras, obviously Sankara’s position which degrades such a qualitative Brahman to the level of the first product of Maya is attacked at the very foundation. We are the more inclined to believe that Sankara has difficulty in deriving support for his doctrine from the Sutras , because of the frequency with* which he begs the question. He puts his opponents out of court and brushes their arguments aside on the ground that these are statements regard¬ ing a merely supposed reality and therefore worthless. Now when a man consistently refuses to take the statements of his opponents at their face value in their intention, the probability is that this face value is not very favourable to him. And a study of the Sutras would seem to bear out the view that Sankara is wise in not making any very direct appeal to them. One of their fundamental positions is that God is not only the originating but also the material cause of the world, in which case it is obvious that the effect would partake of the reality of the cause. A minor consideration is that Sankara himself seems sometimes, and especially in the heat of his conflict with the Buddhists, to accept the distinction made in the Sutras, without seeking to minimize it or explain it away. In reference to Sutra III. 2. 3 he emphasizes the distinction between the dream-world and the waking world, and the contention that the dream-world, as being Maya, is different from the actual waking world—from which it would surely follow that the actual world is not Maya. Sankara, as has been said, temporarily accepts this conclusion. As regards the Upanishads, it may be said that the Maya doctrine certainly does not appear in any explicit form in the THE TEACHING OF SANKARA 71 earlier Upanishads, and there is a good deal to support the position that on the whole they favour a realistic interpretation of the universe. But at the same time it must be admitted that the Maya doctrine is present in germ and that its further development is thoroughly natural and almost inevitable. It is really the result of a desire—pressed indeed to its uttermost— for a philosophical unity of the most rigorous kind. If the con¬ tention has been accepted that nothing is apart from Brahman, and, if it is found difficult to reconcile the plurality with the unity, rigorous logic would seem to demand the denial of the plurality. It probably would not be too much to say that the general teaching of the Upanishads was in favour of such a demand. Thus we seem to ha\ e reached the position that, in respect of the chief parts of his doctrine, Sankara is not a very faithful interpreter of the Sutras, but that on the whole he reproduces and carries farther the main tendencies of the Upanishads. This is very much the position taken up by Thibaut, who has devoted much careful consideration to the problem; and he is supported on both counts by the majority of scholars. Gough, e.g., says that ‘the teaching of Sankara is the natural and legiti¬ mate interpretation of the philosophy of the Upanishads’, 1 and in reference to the Sutras Max Muller says that ‘Sankara’s philosophy, with its unflinching monism, is his own rather than Badarayana’s’. 2 Jacobi 3 says that Sankara does violence to the sense of the Sutras but is nearer to the Upanishads. Garbe 4 takes the opposite view and holds that it is Ramanuja who ‘introduces into Badarayana’s treatise views which are alien to the true Vedantic doctrine’; and he asserts that of the Indian adherents of the Vedanta, ‘three-fourths accept Sankara’s inter¬ pretation of the Brahmasutras Facts hardly bear out this statement. Garbe seems almost to regard the Brahma Sutras and the Upanishads as agreeing on all important points, which is very far from being the case. The truer position would seem to be that while three-fourths of the Vedantists would agree in regarding Sankara as a typical Vedantist, they are not in the 1 Gough, Philosophy of the Upanishads , p. vii. z Muller, S. S. 117. 3 Das Licht vom Osten, 50. 4 E, R. E. XII. 597. 72 Sankara and ramanuja majority of cases willing to allow that he is a faithful interpreter of the Sutras. Indeed, Indian writers are not quite so ready as Deussen and Gough to agree even that Sankara is altogether reliable as an interpreter of the Upanishads. Prof. Radhakrishnan, e.g., takes up an exceedingly cautious attitude on this point; 1 but on the whole in this reference they accept him as a pillar of orthodoxy, and their general attitude would, as we have seen, justify us in regarding him as the main source of material for the exposition and estimation of the Vedanta philosophy. But in regard to the Sutras they are almost all {pace Prof. Garbe) in agreement that he does not faithfully interpret the Sutras. One notable excep¬ tion, however, is Prof. P. D. Shastri, who calls Sankara ‘the best and most satisfactory exponent of Badarayana’s views on the Vedanta problems’. 3 Sir R. G. Bhandarkar, on the other hand, and more representatively, says, ‘There are two doctrines in¬ dicative of the relation of God to the world, the so-called Parinamavada and the Vivartavada. The last is the doctrine of Sankaracharya . . .; while the first is that clearly held by the author of the Sutras.’ 3 He is supported by Prof. S. N. Das Gupta, who is ‘inclined to believe that the dualistic interpreta¬ tions of the Brahmasutras were more faithful to the Sutras than the interpretations of Sankara’. 4 We may then take up generally the position that Sankara re¬ presents a reaction in the direction of the Upanishads and away from the slightly dualistic tendency manifest in the Sutras', and, on this understanding, may proceed to our fuller investigation of Sankara’s views as typical of the Vedanta philosophy. History to a very considerable extent places him in the position of the orthodox exponent, although it does not rule out the considera¬ tion of opposing views. And after all, whatever his affiliations may be, it is with Sankara’s own unfolding of his philosophy that we have mainly to do; for, as Prof. Das Gupta says, ‘a system in the Sutras is weak and helpless as a new born babe’; and the Upanishads themselves awaited through the centuries the coherence of doctrine which only a systematizer could give. 1 Cf. Radhakrishnan, I. 141. 3 Vaishnavisnij p. 160. a P. D. Shastri, 96. 4 Das Gupta, L 421. IV THE APPROACH TO SANKARA’S CENTRAL TEACH¬ ING: PRELIMINARY CONDITIONS; HIS CONCEP¬ TION OF AUTHORITY; THE IDEALISTIC ATTITUDE; HIS RELATION TO BUDDHISM A CCORDING to Sankara, certain preliminary conditions of ^^philosophic study have to be observed. These are broadly similar to those we have already noted in connexion with the Upanishads. For Sankara also the conditions are both external and internal, i.e. they are either largely beyond our control or largely within our control. We find that the spirit of esotericism has persisted even to Sankara’s day, and that of the external conditions one of the most important is that the aspirant should belong to the proper class or caste. The Vedanta is essentially aristocratic. Although its ultimate doctrine is the unity of the Self with Brahman and the denial of the diversity of things, and we might suppose that this denial would apply also to the diverse conditions of human beings, yet from the first this knowledge is jealously guarded as a privilege of only certain sections of the population. The rebirth of the soul which the enlightenment makes possible must have as its counterpart the external ceremony of rebirth, the upanayana ceremony, the investiture of the youth with the sacred thread, for which only the three highest castes are eligible. The Sudras, or lower caste, are rigorously excluded. The Sudra may need this knowledge as much as other men, and he may also be capable of it, but still he must not be allowed the opportunity of acquiring it. 1 This exclusiveness was bound up, as we shall see, with other external conditions such as the Vedantist dependence on the authority of the Veda and upon instruction by a teacher, and we shall discuss these further in connexion with the general question of the place of authority in the Vedanta. In the mean¬ time it may be noted that this limitation of the reading of the 1 Cf. Sankara’s Commentary on Sutra I. 3. 25 ff., where he discusses the question as to who are eligible, and lays down the rule that ‘men only of the three higher castes are . . . not excluded by prohibitions’, and are qualified by being ‘subject to the precepts about the upanayana ceremony and so on\ Cf, S. B. E. XXXIV. 197, and Colebrooke’s Miscellaneous Essays, I. 223. 74 . SANKARA'S CENTRAL TEACHING Vedas was supposed to have been broken only in one or two legendary cases, which were in themselves of doubtful histori¬ city, and which, in any case were of the nature of exceptions proving the rule rather than contradicting it. Sankara himself explicitly accepts the injunction that the Yedas were never to be read in the presence of a Sudra, with the consequence that the knowledge derivable only from the Vedas was a privilege to which the lowest class could not aspire. He states that The mere circumstance of being in a condition of desire does not furnish a reason for qualification if capability is absent. Mere temporal capability again does not constitute a reason for quali¬ fication, spiritual qualification being required in spiritual matters.' 1 And spiritual qualification he defines in the same paragraph as meaning simply not being excluded from the reading of the Vedas. Further he quotes with seeming ac¬ ceptance the stern Vedic prescription that The ears of him who hears the Veda are to be filled with molten lead and lac, “For the Sudra is (like) a cemetery, therefore (the Veda) is not to be read in the vicinity of a Sudra'' '? It is more pleasant and more just, however, to turn from these external restrictions to the internal conditions which Sankara lays down. The importance of these is indicated in the very first Sutra, 'Then, therefore the enquiry into Brahman', especially by the word 'Then'. According to Sankara, 'then' does not at all refer to a preliminary acquaintance with, or performance of, religious works. These, as we shall see later, have only ascetic or propaedeutic value, and do not of themselves bring about any abiding result. The true conditions are purely spiritual, and are enumerated by Sankara as follows: (i) discrimination of what is eternal and what is non-eternal; (2) renunciation of desire for reward both here and hereafter; (3) the attainment of the six means—tranquillity, restraint, renunciation of re¬ ligious ceremonies, patience, concentration, belief; (4) the longing for liberation. A study of these conditions reveals a very pure and elevated conception of the philosophic spirit. There must be as a pre¬ liminary a generally philosophical attitude, a readiness to dis¬ tinguish between the changing and the permanent. There must 1 Cf. S. B. E. XXXIV. 224. 3 lb. 228. PRELIMINARY CONDITIONS 75 be a singleness of aim and no mingling of material ambitions with the pure pursuit after truth. There must be an abandon¬ ment of the sceptical spirit, not to the extent of being the victim of obstructive dogmatism or being unwilling to investigate all problems, but to the extent of being willing to believe that investigation can bring about a result, which result must be viewed in an other-worldly, ascetic rather than humanistic, spirit, properly described by the phrase, ‘longing for liberation’. The ‘six means’ indicate the prevailing state of the mind of the true philosopher. He must be entirely independent of external ceremonies, and patient—to a greater extent even than Aristotle would demand—of the vicissitudes of fortune. He must have his senses wholly under control, and have acquired a Stoic calm. Above all he must be capable of, and practise, concentration— passive to the extent of a recognition that the knowledge of Brahman ‘does not depend on human energy’, but active in the sense that for him concentration means the gathering up of the highest human powers and requires a persistent holding of the divine unity before the mind. Concentration must be care¬ fully distinguished from mere sluggishness of mind. This mixture of the passive and the active attitude is strikingly antici- pative of Spinoza, and it may be noted in passing that Rama¬ nuja in a similar spirit defines meditation as ‘steady remem¬ brance’. 1 Given, then, this spiritual attitude of mind, how does the inquirer proceed ? Is there any assistance from human—or, perhaps from Divine—sources available for him in his quest after God? Will he have to depend on his own resources entirely, or are there authorities which may, nay must, help him? This brings us to the general question of the importance ascribed in the Vedanta to authority . The Place of Authority in the Vedanta We have seen that Sankara took up a fairly submissive attitude in regard to the authority of the Upanishad texts. He considered that he was bound to show the agreement of his main doctrines with these texts. It might turn out that there was agreement also with experience and reason, but such x Cf. S. B. E. XLVIII. 11. 76 Sankara’S central teaching subordinate agreement would be only a consequence of the truth of the doctrine, and neither experience nor reason could be regarded as in any important sense the sources of the doctrine. The ultimate source must lie in authority, reason being given a merely supplementary place and allowed to have validity only ‘in so far as it does not contradict the Vedanta texts’, 1 and in so far as it deals with comparatively minor con¬ siderations. 2, According to Sankara, only perfect knowledge can give release; and perfect knowledge, just because it deals with permanent things and wins universal acceptance, cannot be dependent on mere reasoning. He says in his Commentary on Sutra I. x—11, ‘As the thoughts of men are altogether unfettered, reasoning which disregards the holy texts, and rests on in¬ dividual opinion only, has no proper foundation.’ And again, ‘On account of the diversity of men’s opinions, it is impossible to accept mere reasoning as having a sure foundation.’ 3 Now there has been a tendency both in ancient and modern times for searchers after truth to turn away in disgust from the conflict of opinions and the jarring noises of controversy, and to seek for the region where ‘beyond these voices there is peace’; but Sankara goes farther than most, and asserts in a positive manner that from the nature of the case the highest truth must rest upon authority. In his Commentary on I. 8. 4 we read, ‘The fact of everything having its Self in Brahman cannot be grasped without the aid of the Scriptural passage, “That art Thou”.’ 4 And in I. 8. 11 we read further, ‘The true nature of the cause of the world upon which final emancipation depends, cannot, on account of its abstruseness, even be thought of with¬ out the help of the holy texts; for . . . it cannot become the object of perception because it does not possess qualities such as form and the like, and, as it is devoid of characteristic signs, it does not lend itself to inference and the other means of right knowledge /5 He quotes with approval Kathaka Upanishad I. 2. 9, ‘That doctrine is not to be obtained by argument, but when it is declared by another, then it is easy to understand’. 6 We must reject the ordinary means of proof which rest on 1 Cf. Sutra I. 1.2. 3 Cf. S. B. E. XXXIV. 315. s Ib. 316. 2 Cf. Deussen, 95. 4 Cf. Ib. 23. 6 Ib. 307. HIS CONCEPTION OF AUTHORITY 77 perception and inference; or, if we still retain these psycho¬ logical terms, we must sublimate them. Perception may be transformed into a kind of mystical intuition, similar to sense- perception in its directness; or the two terms may be used in conjunction as indicating the two divisions of the sacred canon, viz. sruti and smnti, ‘hearing’ and ‘remembrance’. According to Sankara’s most usual practice, the first division is equivalent to the older Upanishads, and the second to the Bhagavadgita. The sacred texts not only serve the central purpose of re¬ ligious enlightenment, but have also a more comprehensive usefulness. Even what we should now regard as details of scientific knowledge may be believed on the basis of Scripture. 1 Practical guidance also may be derived from them. In con¬ nexion with III. 1. 26 it is stated that ‘the knowledge of an action being right is based on Scripture only’. Finally, it should be noticed that Sankara does not indulge in any elaborate argument in order to establish the authoritative- ness of the Scriptures; he simply accepts this as something which cannot be gainsaid. ‘Nor can the authoritativeness of the texts’, he says, ‘be proved by inferential reasoning; so that it would be dependent on instances observed elsewhere.’ 3 It has long been the practice of older writers on the Vedanta to lay almost excessive emphasis upon Sankara’s implicit re¬ liance upon authority. They compare him with the scholastics of Europe, and visit him with the contempt which is frequently meted out to such dim-minded medievalists as some of them were. Muir, e.g., speaks of Sankara’s method in a rather lofty manner: ‘These arguments are not likely to seem convincing to any persons but the adherents of the schools from which they have severally emanated. The European student can only look upon these opinions as matters of historical interest, as illustra¬ tions of the course of religious thought among a highly acute and speculative people .’3 A more modern writer to a certain extent redresses the balance by drawing the parallel with the scholastics simply and without depreciation: ‘As Sankara argues with his opponents, his position resembles that of a Scholastic * Cf. Commentary on II. 3.10, S. B. E. XXXVIII. 22, where we are told about the production of water from fire. ■* s. B, E. XXXIV. 23. 3 Sanskrit Texts, III. 209, 7 8 ■ SANKARA’S CENTRAL TEACHING philosopher in medieval Europe. Each believed that he had an infallible authority behind him with which the results of specu¬ lative inquiry must be harmonized. The Christian teacher might start from Aristotle, but he must end with Scripture and the Church. The Hindu might use the methods of reasoning as freely as the Greek, but he must bring their issue into accord with the Veda/ 1 At the same time it must be admitted that Sankara’s apparent abdication of private judgement, his reliance on instruction imparted by another, and his abhorrence of unfettered thought, are disconcertingly suggestive of the narrowness of European medieval philosophy, and seem to place a deep chasm between Vedantic and modern speculation. It would seem at first sight almost impossible to treat as serious philosophy a system which submitted thus tamely to bondage, and it is therefore a matter of considerable importance to inquire whether the bondage is really so complete as might appear on the surface. This is all the more necessary because modern Indian writers are perfectly well aware of the requirements of the philosophic spirit; and, unless we are irresistibly compelled by facts, it would be unfair to bind upon them an inheritance which would limit their speculative freedom. Prof. Radhakrishnan, e.g., in the course of his treatment of the philosophy of the Bhagavadgita, is responsible for the dictum that ‘a half-truth won for ourselves is worth more than a whole truth learned from others’. 3 And in general it may be said that his fellow countrymen are also more or less conscious of the contradiction between the exercise of the philosophic spirit and implicit obedience to authority. Because of loyalty to the spirit of investigation they desire to be free; and yet, if they continue to be loyal also to the tradition of reliance upon Scripture, they would appear to be in bondage. What then can be said of the tradition itself, so far as Sankara is concerned ? Was he with his followers merely a scholastic ad¬ herent of philosophic maxims handed down to them by teachers, or did their adherence to Scriptural authority arise from a deeper motive and one less embarrassing to the freedom of speculative inquiry ? It is, of course, impossible anywhere to get away entirely from 1 Carpenter, 310. V Radhakrishnan, I. 553. HIS CONCEPTION OF AUTHORITY 79 authority, just as impossible as it is to cut oneself altogether loose from one's own past, and there is much truth in what was said of Edward Caird, 'The more original a man, the more heavy the tribute he exacts from the world and the more intimate his dependence. He cannot go before it; he can only set free its significance.' Further, if the reality of the universe is revealing itself to men through the growing knowledge of humanity, we are always at liberty to ask the question whether this revelation is direct or indirect; is it made to each individual afresh or may we not also rely upon the accumulated knowledge handed down by tradition ? And the indirect, massed knowledge may come to us in the form of authority. The general consideration may also be premised that nominal or formal submission to authority has often coexisted with actual speculative freedom, which is left unhindered in practice so long as the authority is not challenged. A recent writer in the Hibbert Journal , 1 e.g., has pointed out— with what justification we shall not presume to say—that the official prescription of doctrinal uniformity in the Roman Catholic Church became obviously restrictive only on the emergence of Modernist doctrines. It is probably true that the demand for credal uniformity became more stringent in India as the result of a reaction from Buddhism, and therefore did not represent a permanently paralysing limitation of thought. Further, in attempting to estimate the fettering effect of authority we have always to keep in mind the degree of ac¬ customedness or naturalness which has been induced. Fetters which have been worn for a long time do not interfere with freedom to the same extent as when they were first imposed; and, further, the liberty of the individual does not seem to be, and is actually not so severely circumscribed when the im¬ position of restrictions arises gradually and naturally from a particular kind of environment. Under such circumstances the irksomeness and feeling of restraint—which subjective effects are all-important in connexion with philosophic independence —seem appreciably lessened, although, of course, we would not go so far as to say that a man who has been a long time in prison, or who is surrounded by others similarly confined, is in the same condition objectively as one who is free. 1 October 1925. 80 SANKARA’S CENTRAL TEACHING It has been already pointed out 1 that the course of philo¬ sophic development in India was different from that of Western philosophy; that in the West one system succeeded another or was built on destructive criticism of the former, whereas in India the same system persisted through the centuries; the main lines of thought were prescribed by tradition; and develop¬ ment could consist only in the interpretation and re-interpreta- tion of existing authorities. The Sutra literature was taken to be typical of the whole. Because of their succinctness, they were unintelligible except to the initiated, and were thus esoteric in their effect and marked the power of authority, while, just because of their unintelligibility, they left room for considerable variety of interpretation and freedom of manipulation. In India it was perhaps truer than of any other land that a great philo¬ sopher could not go before the thought-tradition which he had inherited but could only set free its significance. It might also be useful to draw further attention at this point to the great emphasis which, in the development of Indian thought, is placed upon instruction by a Guru or teacher. We have already noticed Sankara’s approving quotation from the Kdthaka Upanishad I. 2. 9, 3 and the same thought reappears in the Chhandogya Upanishad VII. 25, ‘One who does not attend on a teacher, does not believe’. There is a considerable develop¬ ment in the degree of importance assigned to the teacher, and the growing insistence upon the necessity of such assistance may have been due to Brahmanic influence. But whether this latter cause was operative or not, it is the case that long before Sankara’s day the presence of a teacher had become the recog¬ nized background of Indian thought. The dramatic setting of the Upanishads is largely constituted by the search for a teacher who will reveal the deepest mysteries; and, when he has been found, unbounded devotion and the most minute practical service is demanded of the pupil. The persistence of the attitude may be traced even to the present day . A recent Indian writer thus speaks in reference to the highest knowledge, ‘The sole source of this knowledge is a clear and accurate under¬ standing of the Vedic text,“Tl^at thou art”; but, however much one may analyse its meaning by means of his own reason or with 1 p. 9. 2 p. 76. HIS CONCEPTION OF AUTHORITY 81 the aid of commentaries, the direct realization of the self cannot take place unless the Yedic text in question reaches the student through the mouth of a spiritual teacher. 51 And in the course of the development and as a result of it, devotion to truth and devotion to the Guru become almost synonymous. The latter comes to be regarded as well advanced on the way to deification; his personal authority is thus enhanced, and the principle of authority becomes more and more deeply engrained in the mental attitude of the Indian seeker after truth. Whether this is altogether advantageous or not has been very seriously questioned. One writer speaks thus of the reverence for the Guru : Tt is a training not in self-reliance and inde¬ pendence of judgement, but in subservience to authority and reverence for what is established, just because it is established. 5 * An Indian writer is even more emphatic as regards the effect upon the consciousness of the people. Mr. D. N. Pal says, ‘They had lost the power of independent judgement long ago— they had left it in the hands of the Brahman from time im¬ memorial; and the result we all know to our cost 5 .3 But whether desirable or not, the attitude spread to the whole environment. We have already noted Sankara’s acceptance of the principle that morality may be a matter of prescription, and this idea is deeply rooted in the life of the people. It is implied in their conception of dharma. A recent writer says, ‘The idea of dharma is, like the Roman pie to, very closely bound up with the details as well as with the general spirit of a man’s daily life and conduct as a member of the family or caste group. As a rule his duty is so clearly indicated by custom that he can be in no doubt about it.’ And again, ‘Actions are not right or wrong in their nature but only as they conform, or fail to conform, to a standard of propriety set up by general consent.’ 4 We thus see that authority is not something abruptly and obtrusively imposed upon a man from without, but something which almost imperceptibly emerges from, and gathers up, the spirit of the whole environment. The pressure of it upon the individual is thus softened by its exceeding naturalness. In 1 Venkataramanan, * Sankara’s Philosophy of Samsara in Three Great Acharyas , p. in. 2 McKenzie, Hindu Ethics, 50. 3 Pal, 65.** 4 Margaret M. Urquhart, JFbmtf/z of Bengal^ 33 and 57, G ' ' 82 Sankara’S central teaching addition to this it is modified by certain tendencies towards valuation which save it from being merely a blind submission to detailed prescriptions having authority just because they were traditional. The ancient seers were considered to be worthy of respect, not simply because they were old but because of their pre-eminent merits, and for the reason that it was at least con¬ ceivable that men of former ages might have been capable of more direct intuition of God than was possible for their descen¬ dants of a later day. Sankara explicitly takes this view, ‘What is for us imperceptible was perceptible for the ancients: thus it is recorded that Vyasa and others used to meet the Gods and Rishis face to face. ... We must therefore believe that the ancients, in consequence of pre-eminent merits, held visible converse with Gods and Rishis.’ 1 There is here at least a suggestion of a transition from the conception of the authority of age to that of the authority of the specialist in religion. There is further a recognition of an inherent satisfactoriness in the contents of the texts. They shine by their own light and have independent authority by reason of the character of their con¬ tents. They are convincing by their intrinsic value. 1 Now it is but a short step from subjective satisfaction to evaluation on a metaphysical and more objective basis. The Vedanta passages come to have value, not merely as authorities, but because they have for their objects ‘firmly established thin gs’. Their fundamental aim is ‘not to alter existing things but to make them appear as they are’. 3 But the real is the permanent, and the next very closely connected movement of thought is to the idea that the Scriptures, just because they deal with reality and therefore with the eternal, must themselves be eternal. They cannot be the work of a personal author; and their validity must be recognized by raising them above any phenomenal changes and placing them on the level of the nou- menal which is independent of change. This conception of the eternity of the Vedas is supported by repeated discussions of the eternity of the words of which they are composed and even 1 Quoted by Deussen, $. V. 38. 3 Of. ‘The passages of Scripture about the negation of all difference have a meaning which leaves nothing more to be wished for.’ S.B.E. XXXVIII, 395 - 3 Cf. Commentary on Prasna U. VI. 3. HIS CONCEPTION OF AUTHORITY 83 of the sounds which the words indicate. There is alleged to be a natural and not merely conventional relation between words and that which they signify; words have an intrinsic denotation which is the essence of their authority. 1 Further, words themselves acquire deeper metaphysical signi¬ ficance when, on the ground that they are injunctive (i.e. com¬ manding things to be done) or that they are purposive (indicating plans of action), they are allied with the idea of creativeness. Prof. Paterson in his recent book refers to the early association of word with creative energy, ‘The oral rite was felt to be highly charged with mysterious energy.' ‘ The uttered “must”,’ as Marett observes, ‘is the very type of spiritual projectile, for nothing indicates an imperative more clearly, cutting it away from the formative matrix of thought and launching it on its free career, than the spoken word, and nothing finds its way home to another mind more sharply.’ 2 When this idea is associated with divine power, we are on the edge of a conception very similar to that which permits the ascription of cosmological significance to the syllable Om, and also to the less symbolic, but much deeper, concept embodied in the Logos doctrine of St. John’s Gospel, ‘In the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God, and the Word was God.’ 3 The earlier Mlmdmsa Sutras were content to prove the eternity of the Word, but the Vedanta Sutras definitely connect with this the idea of the Word as an emanation from God, and as indicating divine activity. God revealed himself in the sound forms and sent forth his activity into the planning and accom¬ plishment of the world. Now if we think in this way, we can readily conceive of the process by which reverence for the Scriptures became reverence for the Word in general, and reverence for the Word became reverence for the Divine energy behind it. The Scriptures are invested with an almost metaphysical reality of their own, and respect for authority becomes, in idea at least, reverence for God. The Word heard by man is the plan followed by God, as 1 Cf. Farquhar, 125, ‘The absolute authority of the Veda requires for its establishment the doctrine of its eternity, and that leads in turn to the doctrine of the eternity of sound, and the indefeasible connexion between the sound of a word and its meaning/ a Paterson, Nature of Religion> 390, 3 John i. 1. 84 SANKARA’S CENTRAL TEACHING well as the energy through which the plan is realized. We pass from the region of blind submission to authority to that of religious devotion to a supreme Reality. When, further, we remember what was regarded by Sankara as the central doctrine of the tradition handed down to him, viz. the assertion of the essential unity of the Divine and the human, we may trace a further step in the direction of the substantializing and internalizing of authority. After all, Sankara did not go to the sacred texts for anything in the nature of detailed instruc¬ tions, but just for support of this central doctrine, and it was the ' assertion of this truth which, above everything else, he found in the texts. These served as a framework to this truth, and when the truth was discovered it was even possible that the frame¬ work might be discarded. The contents, the supreme contents of the Scriptures, were all that mattered, and their purpose was just the encouraging of an apprehension of the One Reality, in the apprehension of which the seeker submitted to no external authority but realized the essence of his own Self. San¬ kara himself gives explicit permission for this transcending of scriptural authority, although it must be admitted that in one particular case he does so under circumstances which are slightly suggestive of a desire to escape from a logical contradiction. 1 It may be noted that in this connexion Ramanuja pertinently observes that such a concession weakens Sankara’s whole position, inasmuch as, if Scripture is itself founded upon ne¬ science and disappears when nescience disappears, it cannot be used to correct the errors of ordinary perception. 2 In all this discussion we have been concerned simply to establish what we consider to be a position of some importance, viz. that it is necessary to take a broader view than in some quarters is customary of Sankara’s conception of authority, and that in the last resort his subjection to authority is not necessarily inimical to the philosophical spirit. There is much truth in the contention of Prof. S. N. Tattvabhushan that Sankara’s ‘appeal to Scripture is not as to an external authority to be blindly re- 1 Cf. Commentary on Sutras , IV. i. 3, ‘Nor do we mind your objecting that, if perception &c., cease to be valid, scripture itself ceases to be so, for this conclusion is just what we assume. . . . We ourselves assume that, when knowledge springs up, scripture ceases to be valid.* S. B.E. XXXVIII. 340. % Cf. S. B. E. XLVIIL 73. HIS CONCEPTION OF AUTHORITY 85 ceived, but as to a valuable help to the attainment of true wisdom—wisdom which is attainable by every true seeker after truth '. 1 2 As we try to understand the attitude of Sankara we shall find that we are frequently not far distant from the idea that religion cannot be merely a subjective product of individual imagination, but must be a response of the best within us to the best without, this ‘best without us' being discovered to be of the same spiritual quality and essence as the ‘best within 5 . 3 We must next inquire as to the influence which Sankara’s views of authority had upon his method. Although, as we have seen, his speculative freedom may not have been greatly re¬ stricted, yet it cannot be denied that he did not always live up to the ideal we have suggested as associable with his attitude, and that his acceptance of authority had to a certain extent a hampering effect. It seems to lead, e.g., to a slight unfairness in his treatment of his opponents. He assumes at the outset that he has the monopoly of authority, and that, therefore, while he may appeal from perception to authority, it is not permissible for his opponents to do so. The latter must rely wholly on experience and can find no escape from its contra¬ dictions. He alone occupies the privileged position. Further, because of his respect for his authorities, Sankara feels himself constrained to follow the order of the Sutras . In¬ stead of constructing his arguments on lines of his own and arranging them so that they may lead most naturally to his main conclusions, he has to follow a somewhat tortuous course, winding in and out amongst the topics suggested by the Sutras , and the main doctrines have to be established, as it were, by the way. Moreover, seeing that the main object formally was to show agreement of the doctrines with the Vedanta texts, the internal consistency of the arguments fell to a position of secondary importance, and the necessity of so arranging them as to bring out their coherence and completeness was not so keenly felt as it might otherwise have been . 3 Also, as Deussen points out in the same connexion, that fondness for dialectical disputation which so often arises in association with minute 1 Three Great Acharyas, 76. 2 Cf. Prof; J." Arthur Thomson in Religions of the Empire, p. 300. 3 Cf. Deussen, *$?. FV220. 86 SANKARA’S CENTRAL TEACHING textual interest and desire to prove a scriptural basis led to a certain want of proportion. Arguments for or against parti¬ cular positions were bandied to and fro without sufficient regard to the importance of the disputed point relatively to the whole. But the chief difficulty for Sankara in the application of his doctrine of authority was caused by the want of harmony amongst the Upanishad texts themselves. It was easy when Scripture was in conflict with sense perception to decide dog¬ matically in favour of the former, but when Scripture conflicted with Scripture, what was to be done? Under such circum¬ stances it was clearly not to be hoped that all the texts should support directly Sankara’s philosophical position. Yet if his authority was to remain unimpaired, it was necessary that they should at least appear to do so; and if their own intrinsic re¬ liability was to remain undamaged, it was necessary that dis¬ crepancies should be removed. Sankara was ready with two devices—both of which have been popular with writers through¬ out the ages, when their canonical authorities have caused them searchings of heart. The one is the principle of earlier and later, to which we have already briefly referred in discussing Sankara s affiliation to the Sutras, He applies it with great vigour to the question of the distinction between the qualitative and non-qualitative Brahman, on the basis of the principle which he lays down as follows : ‘There being a conflict between the two passages, we . . . decide that the texts referring to Brahman as devoid of qualities are of greater force, because they are later in order than those which speak of Brahman as having qualities. Thus everything is settled.’ 1 The man of straw has to be set up before he can be satisfactorily knocked down. In application of the principlewe find, e.g., that a passage such as Mundaka Upanishad I. i. 9, ‘From him who perceives all and knows all, whose brooding consists of knowledge, from him is born Hiranyagarbha, names, form and matter’, seems to favour the qualitative view; whereas Brihadaranyaka Upani¬ shad III. 4. 2, ‘Thou couldst not see the true seer of sight’, &c., seems to favour the non-qualitative. Unfortunately, as we have also seen, the application of the principle does not always work 1 S. B. E. XLVIII. 26. HIS CONCEPTION OF AUTHORITY 87 out in favour of Sankara, for we find that, even in the same Upanishad, passages with a negative tendency precede those with a positive tendency. 1 Sankara’s method of reconciliation becomes more interesting, and at the same time more elusive, when he adopts the second device. We have already referred to it as one of the a priori considerations affecting our estimate of his reliability as an interpreter of the Sutras and the Upanishads. It is based on the relation between the literal and the figurative, and ulti¬ mately on the distinction which he draws between the exoteric and the esoteric and between lower and higher orders of knowledge. He makes great use of these distinctions and finds them very convenient for the purpose of removing discrepancies. We are here concerned with his use of the distinction between lower and higher knowledge only in connexion with the recon¬ ciliation of isolated and apparently contradictory texts; and it would be unfair at this stage to prejudge the question whether the distinction is in general ultimately defensible. As a method of adjusting differences it may be said to proceed on the prin¬ ciple that, if a passage contradicts his main doctrine, it will have to be interpreted figuratively, whereas, if it is in agreement with his central views, it may be taken literally; and in passing we may repeat the observation that, on the whole, Sankara finds himself compelled to make much fuller use of figurative inter¬ pretation than does Ramanuja. As an illustration of Sankara’s method we may take his refutation of the Sankhya doctrine of the origin of the world in a non-intelligent pradhana . He points out in his Commentary on Sutra I. 1. 6 that we must not make use of metaphor in order to attribute the term ‘self’ to the pradhana or non-intelligent principle. But in connexion with another Sutra, viz. II. 4. 2, he claims the right to interpret a Sutra figuratively if it occurs in the purvapaksha , or in relation to a doctrine which has to be refuted, while on the other hand if it occurs in a siddhanta Sutra, or in relation to a doctrine which has to be established, he retains the right to interpret literally? And in general, if difficulties occur in connexion with the created world, he is inclined to have recourse to the idea that the world 1 Cf. Mundaka U. X. 1. 6 and I. 1. 9. > Cf. B\E. XXXVIII. 77. 88 SANKARA'S CENTRAL TEACHING has been created only in a figurative sense and that, therefore, any difficulties which may arise are difficulties only from an exoteric point of view. Sankara’s Idealistic Attitude t Having considered Sankara’s statement of preliminary con¬ ditions and his attitude to, and application of, the principle of authority, we may now turn to his method of approach to his main problem. His procedure might be described as an ex¬ pression of the idealistic spirit in philosophy, in so far as this implies a turning away from the immediate and naively realistic pronouncements of common sense. Deussen finds in him an exemplification of the fundamental attitude of metaphysics— that attitude without which metaphysics cannot exist, arising out of dissatisfaction with the immediate data of the senses, discontent with merely empirical and narrowly scientific in¬ vestigation, and an earnest desire to penetrate beyond the appearances of things to the innermost secret of real being. In the fleeting experiences of ordinary perception, in the changing contents of space and time, in the unending succession of causes and effects, there can be no rest for the human spirit. Sankara has embarked on that unchanging quest in which philosophy and religion are united, driven onwards by that insistent consciousness the very essence of which, as Hegel tells us, is the parting from and forsaking of what is immediate, what is finite , and the seeking for that home-country of the soul which, again in Hegel’s words, is £ the region of eternal truth, of eternal rest, of eternal peace 5 . 1 And yet, in our fully justified endeavour to place Sankara in the main line of philosophical succession, we must not allow our description of the general philosophical attitude to be coloured by an anticipation of what we conceive Sankara’s particular philosophy to be. Because we may have a preliminary con¬ sciousness that Sankara teaches a doctrine of empirical illu- sionism, we must not take it for granted that all philosophy is rooted in a similar belief. Neither, on the other hand, should we allow ourselves to take the most negative possible view of San¬ kara s concept of illusion, under the influence of any general 1 Hegel, Philosophy of Religion , i and 106. THE IDEALISTIC ATTITUDE 89 reflection that in this matter he is in agreement with all philoso¬ phers of consequence. It may not be true that all philosophers of consequence start with a theory of illusion, and it may also turn out to be doubtful whether Sankara’s own doctrine in this respect is so extreme as it is often supposed to be. We cannot help thinking that Deussen has been neglectful of cautionary considerations of this kind, and that his conception of what philosophy has been, is, and always ought to be may have in¬ fluenced unduly his particular interpretation of the Vedanta philosophy. He describes, e.g., the disposition to metaphysics as ‘a more or less clear consciousness that all empirical in¬ vestigation and knowledge amounts in the end only to a great deception, grounded in the nature of our knowing faculties, to open our eyes to which is the task of metaphysics’. 1 On the same page he asserts dogmatically that this ‘more or less clear consciousness “became” a conviction’ in the teaching of Kant. And with this view of philosophy as a basis he proceeds to erect his System of the Vedanta. Now it may be true that, e.g., Descartes, the father of modern Western philosophy, began with the supposition that all the things he saw around him might be fictitious, and that he advocated a preliminary universal scepticism. 2 But surely a preliminary supposition is very different from a dogmatic conclusion, and to say that our senses may deceive us is very different from asserting that they actually lead us astray, or that all empirical data are illusory. Neither is it legitimate, as we shall afterwards have occasion to point out more fully, to de¬ scribe Kant’s position as dogmatically negative rather than as provisionally agnostic. But what we wish specially to protest against at the present juncture is the deduction which Deussen draws from his general philosophical position, and his resulting inclination to prejudice the issue by suggesting that, if Sankara is to be placed alongside of the greatest philosophers of all ages, it must be expected at the outset that he will reach purely negative conclusions, according to which the whole empirical world will be swept away as altogether illusory. Sankara’s general idealistic position is clearly stated in the summary of his doctrines given by Ramanuja, ‘Therefore know 1 Deussen, S, V. 48. s Cf. Meditation, II. 90 SANKARA’S CENTRAL TEACHING that all particular things like rocks, oceans, hills, and so on, have proceeded from intelligence. . . . Nothing whatever, at any place or any time, exists apart from intelligence. 51 This de¬ pendence of so-called objective reality upon mind is a funda¬ mental assumption. Idealism, in almost all systems associated with the term, has both an objective and a subjective phase, sometimes the one and sometimes the other receiving the greater emphasis. In connexion with the Vedanta it may be easier to get a clear-cut statement of the objective than of the subjective phase, but we believe that subjective idealism is the natural way of approach to idealism of a negative and cosmical character, and that the Vedanta, as interpretated by Sankara, is no exception to this rule. If the world of experience is made up of unsubstantial things such as dreams are made of, it would seem necessary, in order to fill out the conception, to view this world both as a projection of the individual self and as the out¬ come of cosmic imagining. The first point of view, giving centrality to the consciousness of the ordinary perceiver, would seem to have temporal priority in the thought of the individual philosopher. This idea of the centrality of consciousness is emphasized by Sankara, in the summary of his doctrines given by Ramanuja. He has been attacking the realists for having failed to give due consideration to the power of consciousness and he proceeds: ‘The fact is, that in perceiving colour and other qualities of things, we are not aware of a “shining forth 55 as an attribute of these things, and as something different from consciousness; nor can the assumption of an attribute of things called “light 55 , or “shining forth 55 be proved in any way, since the entire em¬ pirical world itself can be proved only through consciousness. ... Consciousness is independent of any other thing, because, through its connexion with other things, it is the cause of their attributes and of the empirical judgements concerning them. . . . Consciousness is itself the cause of its own “shining forth 55 as well as of the empirically observed shining forth of objects such as jars and the like. 5 2 It may seem strange that we should quote from Ramanuja this statement of Sankara’s position, but the Great Purvapakska , 1 S. B. E. XLVIII. 23. Cf. S. B. E. XLVIII. 28. 112 THE ULTIMATE UNITY we must also remember that he is non-Being in respect of any empirical conception of existence. We may call him thought (cit), but we must use this in accordance with the general prin¬ ciple just stated, to signify that Brahman is nothing lower than thought, and we must refrain from ascribing to him any con¬ sciousness with which we are familiar in our experience. Es¬ pecially must we be careful not to think of him as the subject of cognition, because this would imply a differentiated object, and, on the other side of the relation, would also imply a distinction between the knower and the consciousness which he possesses. Brahman is consciousness pure and simple, not a conscious sub¬ ject jp/ws his consciousness. Any difference between conscious¬ ness and the conscious subject would have to be ascribed to an unreal principle of egoity. Similarly, we may ascribe to him the predicate of bliss (ananda), but we must remember that it is bliss ‘without the fruition of happiness’. It is not the awareness of satisfied endeavour, it is rather the assured calm of absolute self-absorption, the conscious gradual sinking into Being, the oncoming' sense of infinity, without disturbance of particular thought or particular interest. But having discovered to some extent what Sankara intends by identity with this pure Being, whom for the present we must leave in such a state of purity and vagueness that it is difficult, though not impossible, to distinguish it from Nothing, we must next ask how this identification is to be accomplished. This leads us to consider that fundamental distinction between lower and higher knowledge, through which Sankara arrives at the consummation of his endeavour. The point which we have specially to keep in view is the degree of abruptness of the distinction. If the goal is negative, it is probable that the ap¬ proach to it will be by means of abrupt negation, but we have also to keep in mind the other possibility that the negation of the lower may be its fulfilment and that the negative may be the cutting edge of a positive. Sankara’s view would seem to be that the differences between the ordinary and the truly philosophical points of view are so striking that the processes and results with which we are con¬ cerned in the two spheres cannot be put into the same class. In THE TWO ORDERS OF KNOWLEDGE 113 the one class we have a body of knowledge which is altogether exoteric, a lower doctrine (apara vidya), and in the other an illuminating, momentary, and yet eternal, flash of combined intuition and revelation, yielding—if ever it can be fixated—the higher doctrine (para vidya) which alone attains to truth. In the first group we may put all our ordinary experiences, our search after location and date, causes and effects, with all the practical consequences which flow from this conglomeration of information, all the gropings of our reasoning faculty, and all the speculative problems which remain unsolved so long as we try to lighten the darkness by the flickering candle of our own powers of intellect. Within this lower knowledge we are helpless prisoners, and cannot by any means save our souls. We may pass restlessly from one phase of experience to another, but cannot shake ourselves free from the degradation of the ordinary. We may by strenuousness rise painfully and slowly upwards to¬ wards God, but at the end it is not the Absolute or the Ultimate into whose presence we come. We have reached only what might be described as a ‘service 5 God, who may be suitable as an object of worship and with whom we may desire indefinitely continued communion. But he will not be the goal of our soul’s endeavour, because we shall still be ascribing qualities to him, and these qualities will hang like veils between us and the ultimate reality. And whilst the God to whom we attain, and whom we think we know, continues in misleading distinctness before us as an object, we shall yet remain in separation from him, and shall not reach that consummation of unity which constitutes our release and our salvation. And on the other side we may place that higher wisdom through which God and man are so closely brought together that we can hardly decide whether we ought to speak of revelation or of intuition—so inevitably does the descending of the Divine come to meet the uprising of the human heart , the best without us mingling with the best within. The product of this com¬ mingling is a knowledge of that Reality which lies hidden be¬ neath all the experiences of man, that God without qualities hidden behind that fullness of divine quality which we take as the object of our worship. In this knowledge is our peace, for we are delivered from all that perplexes us in our outward 1" „ 4 THE ULTIMATE UNITY gazing upon the world, and the God whom we are in search of no longer stands over against us in a separating distinctness, but, through that vagueness in which all outlines are blurred, passes from the outward to the inward and welcomes us to a unity which we discover has always been the truth of things, even though at this critical point of transition it may be pre¬ sented with the abruptness of a new discovery. As has been said, in such knowledge intuition and revelation become merged in one; and so the position of Sankara recalls the old texts of the Mundaka Upanishad, where it is said that ‘when a man’s nature has become purified by the serene light of knowledge, then he sees him, meditating upon him as without parts’, and, again, ‘the wise, having reached Him who is omnipresent everywhere, devoted to the Self, enter into him wholly ’. 1 And to those who are familiar with the New Testament it suggests that wisdom which is both pure and peaceable, which is from above,—a gift which ‘cometh down from the Father of lights, with whom is no variableness, neither shadow of turning ’. 3 The contrast between the two divisions is made so definite by Sankara that the points of view become almost exclusive of one another. We reach the unity only by passing very resolutely from the one kind of experience to the other, and when we escape from the land of bondage we carry nothing with us. We are led to ask the question whether this abrupt distinction and defini¬ tive transition is either natural or necessary ? Is it even possible, or, if it is possible, is it desirable? Must we have separation as well as distinction ? The distinction certainly gathers up within itself and con¬ tinues two common differentiations, viz. between the ordinary and the scientific point of view, and between the scientific and the purely philosophical. With the first distinction we are but little concerned, as the necessity for it would be a matter of agreement amongst all who have ceased to be the slaves of custom and convention and prudential maxims. It is with the second distinction that we have to do, and here also there is considerable agreement about its necessity, and controversy has reference only to the degree of abruptness with which the distinction ought to be made. 1 Mundaka U . III. I. 8 and III. 2. 5. 2 James I. 17 THE TWO ORDERS OF KNOWLEDGE 115 In these days no one would contend that merely scientific categories are adequate to reality, but all down through the ages also—from the Upanishads, through Sankara, right down to modern Western thinkers—we find a continuous depreciation of mere knowledge of a purely scientific character. In the Brihada- r any aka Upanishadlll. 5. 1 we read,‘Therefore let a Brahmana, after he has done with learning, wish to stand by a childlike state.’ It is true that Max Muller, mainly because of a suspicion that ‘knowledge of babes’ may be ‘a Christian rather than an Indian idea’, 1 translates the passage ‘Therefore let a Brahmana, after he has done with learning, wish to stand by real strength’. But even Max Muller interprets ‘real strength’ as meaning ‘knowledge . . . which enables us to dispense with all other knowledge’, and the translation which implies ‘childlikeness’ is supported by such authorities as Gough and Deussen. Still more striking is the support which is given to this interpretation by Sankara himself, who takes for granted the meaning of ‘childlikeness’, refutes certain mistaken deductions from it, and expounds the passage as follows, ‘The meaning of the clause under discussion thus is, Let him be free from guile, pride and so on, not manifesting himself by a display of knowledge, learning and virtuousness, just as a child . . . does not strive to make a display of himself before others.’ 2 Thus in both ancient and medieval Indian thought there is testimony to the idea that he who would enter the kingdom of the knowledge of God must become as a little child. And if we wish to bring the testimony down to modem times we may unite in relation to this attitude both East and West, and find the lesson of humility in respect of knowledge impressively'taught by one of the fore¬ most scientists of modem times. ‘Science’, says Prof. J. Arthur Thomson, ‘gives us no more than descriptive formulations, and we strain at the limitations of our faculties when, as Sir Thomas Browne said, “we think of things that thoughts do but tenderly touch”. Even when the minor mysteries disappear before Science, the fundamental mysteriousness of nature remains, unless we are content or positivistically compelled to sink the big questions altogether. Even when we reduce everything 1 Cf. *S. B. E. XV. 130 and Radhakrishnan. I. 177. * S.B.E. XXXVIII. 326. 1 x6 THE ULTIMATE UNITY measurable and ponderable to the lowest common denomina- tors—the irreducibles of the day, like electrons and protons— our experience is not thereby rationalized. We seek for a synop¬ tic vision, in the light of the Greatest Common Measure. When the half-gods go, the God arrives.’ 1 But as we probe farther into the matter and attempt to repre¬ sent more definitely the central teaching of Sankara, we find that he reaches conclusions in regard to which it would be difficult to claim general agreement. We have hints not merely of the necessity of a higher point of view but of its total separa¬ tion from the lower. The particular character of the difficulty may be set forth by a phrase which Deussen uses when intro¬ ducing this very topic of Sankara’s distinction between the exoteric and the esoteric. The German philosopher says that metaphysics must ‘in many cases renounce results that can be clearly represented’, and adds, ‘All this demands great power and habit of abstraction, attainable only by a few ' 2 Now this may be quite true, but the way in which the statement is put suggests an excessive emphasis upon the abstraction and nega¬ tion, and implies an abrupt cutting off of the higher from the lower. Deussen thus prepares our minds for the acceptance of the definite separation which is to be found in Sankara himself, and for which, it may be noted in passing, the latter derives little support either from the Upanishads or the Sutras . Fur¬ ther, the words we have italicized seem to suggest an aristocratic exclusiveness—perhaps not altogether unconnected with tradi¬ tional caste-divisions—which results in placing the two kinds of knowledge side by side, stressing their opposition rather than their relationship, and assigning possession of them to different classes of people rather than to different stages in the same mental development. The idea of privilege thus creeps in, an idea similar to that which Lotze so severely criticizes in the 1 In Religions of the Empire , 413. We may compare also the attitude of Schopenhauer, expressive, however, of a very different mood: ‘This is the state which I have described above as necessary for the knowledge of the Idea, as pure contemplation, as sinking oneself in perception, losing oneself in the object, forgetting all individuality, succeeding that kind of knowledge which follows only the principle of sufficient reason and comprehends only rela¬ tions.’ We perhaps find something of the same tendency in the abhor¬ rence of the merely moralistic point of view which is expressed by such writers as Bosanquet. 3 Deussen, 97 [italics mine]. THE TWO ORDERS OF KNOWLEDGE 117 concluding chapter of his Philosophy of Religion, where he con¬ trasts the attitude of the man who attempts to make a symbolic creed yield up its meaning to intellectual inquiry with that of the man who considers the creed as it stands sufficient for the needs of the crowd while he himself occupies somewhat dis¬ dainfully the vantage ground of the higher point of view. We are here concerned, however, not with the social but with the intellectual aspect of the matter, and it is difficult not to connect the distinction with a certain intellectual pride and a contempt for the lower—a looking on it as unworthy in itself or as sus¬ ceptible only of negation rather than of elevation or transforma¬ tion. In this way, in the sphere of the intellect renunciation or negation takes the place of sublimation or transcendence. There is no natural point of contact between the two kinds of knowledge, and the higher is slightly patronizing in reference to the lower. Sankara himself finds it impossible to conceive of co-opera¬ tion between the two orders. They are mutually exclusive. ‘How can the cognition of unity’, he asks, ‘remove the manifold if both are true?’ 1 They are as separate as dream and waking reality; and just as when we awake we do not take the trouble to modify a dream, but entirely sublate it, so, when the true knowledge arises, ‘the world of effects with the means and objects of right knowledge and its results of action is untrue’. 3 In the same way, just as we look upon the crises of a dream as harmless, so may we look upon the world of the ordinary in the same kindly but intellectually lethargic way. ‘As long as true knowledge does not present itself, there is no reason why the ordinary course of secular and religious activity should not hold on undisturbed .’3 No reason! And yet we are told that it is a far country where the soul exists as an alien and a ‘wanderer’, and it seems a pity that the soul should be so lightly permitted to continue its wanderings. Further, this abrupt separation leads to consequences which are not all of them desirable. If there are two sharply distin¬ guished points of view, we shall very likely be tempted to think that difficulties which arise from one point of view maybe disre¬ garded while we flee unconcernedly to the other. Mr. D. N. Pal 1 S.B.E. XXXIV. 323. ‘Ib. 324. 3 lb. 324. ii8 THE ULTIMATE UNITY unconsciously suggests a danger of this kind when he tells us that ‘Sankara has found a wonderful way out’. Of course to deny the validity of certain groups of disconcerting conclusions by pointing out that the procedure by which we arrive at these conclusions is unnecessary or mistaken, is simply another way of saying that the conclusions are not ultimately satisfactory. But, all the same, an effort to deal directly with the particular difficulties which the empirical conclusions leave unresolved would give an impression of greater philosophical courage, whilst, on the other hand, the method of escape, with slightly contemptuous backward glance, is apt to encourage a certain laissez-faire attitude to the difficulties left behind. The higher point of view becomes so detached from the lower that it is unable by its insistent truthfulness to force the latter to yield up a solution of its contradictions. If the lower knowledge is de¬ spised as being on the level of dream-experiences, we become disposed to leave it alone in its confusions. If we dream of a man with two heads, we do not trouble when we awake to point out that such a monstrosity is impossible on physiological grounds. We simply dismiss it as a dream, and leave it alone with the truth which it had as an actual element in the dream experience. In this way the standard is lowered, and we are compelled to admit an element of truth in Puroshottama Misra’s rather cynical remark, ‘in this system, which maintains that everything transcends explanation, unreasonableness is no objection’. 1 Things may be accepted as true up to a certain point and left there. Although we have a vague feeling that they are not wholly true, we do not trouble to challenge the half- truth we have already got and compel it to yield up the fuller truth. In the language of logic we might say that the separation we are considering forces us to use a hypothesis which is con¬ tinually changing its ground, and thus failing to conform to the rules of a good hypothesis. A hypothesis, if it is to be considered legitimate, should not be employed on one level and then, be¬ cause of the greater difficulties in which it involves us, altogether abandoned on a higher level while still permitted to be valid on the lower. It should be carried through and tested by its adequacy in dealing with the whole situation. Yet Soankara’s 1 Quoted in Goreh’s Rational Refutation, 355. THE TWO ORDERS OF KNOWLEDGE 119 argument against the Buddhists, while to a large extent its logical consistency may be upheld, is not wholly free from objections of this sort. And for the same reason we may also have to view somewhat critically certain implications of his doctrine of Maya, and also the argument by which he seeks to prove that God is not responsible for the disconcerting evil of the world. There is another unfortunate consequence. The conception of the negative and indescribable character of ultimate reality is often the outcome of that desperate search for a mysterious and elusive substance beyond qualities of which Prof. Pringle- Pattison has so well shown the futility in his Idea of God . Sankara is right in his contention that scientific knowledge must fail in such a quest, but his method conceals both from himself and from others the true conclusion that the quest is really a hopeless one. He rather suggests that, though such a reality cannot be reached on the empirical level, it may be reached by the higher knowledge. The empirical investigator is practically told that he has failed because he has been searching in the wrong place and not because he has been searching for the wrong thing. He is prevented from discovering for himself the barrenness of the mystical substance for which he is searching by having it suggested to him that he should leave the inquiry to that higher knowledge to which he has not yet attained. And, in addition to this, the higher knowledge also encourages him in his abstract view, for there is associated with it the idea of vagueness rather than of definiteness, and even he who has attained to it has to be content with the abstract and the negative and the undefined. He is not encouraged to press onwards in the quest for an ultimate unity which will provide an explanation of the empirical variety of the world. He is apt to fall into the error of those who, as Prof. Laird puts it, ‘mistake a useless spectre for the last word in profundity, and often advance the extraordinary doctrine that truth is an incomprehensible reality, while the thing that we know is a comprehensible unreality’. 1 Although it may be true, as Prof. K. Shastri so frequently points out in his book upon the Adwaita Philosophy, that Sankara’s aim was to show that the details of the world are 1 Idea of ' the Soul, 60. 120 THE ULTIMATE UNITY nothing apart from Brahman, the separation between the two orders of knowledge compels Sankara to run the serious risk of coming to the conclusion that they are nothing at all. And the vagueness of the apprehension of unity with the undifferenced Brahman which the higher knowledge affords, is apt to make us forget that the goal of philosophy is to discover the infinitely transcendent source of all things which will at once give them reality and explain them. The procedure we have been studying is rather a temptation to turn the true ideas of the ‘infinite 5 and the ‘inexhaustible 5 into the ‘inaccessible 5 . Vagueness has re¬ ceived a benediction through being connected with a higher order of knowledge. Further, when we are thus left in presence of the merely characterless and abstract, we find it difficult to maintain spiritual conceptions in their requisite purity. Physical concep¬ tions, which, in general, philosophy has to make constant efforts to transcend, reassert themselves. We become less aware of and less appreciative of the importance of the activity of consciousness. Our desire indeed is-—if at this level we can still have desires—to rise to something higher than conscious¬ ness, but the danger is that, in presence of this vague ultimate which we have detached from experience, we may fall below, instead of rise above, the level of consciousness and reach unity by way of the unconscious. Intense and concentrated contem¬ plation is no doubt the ideal which Sankara has in view, but we cannot help feeling that, in common with all mystics, as Prof. Pringle-Pattison has pointed out, he is to some extent inclined first of all to treat contemplation as very nearly equi¬ valent to absorption, and then to give to the latter term a meaning derived from observation of the mixture of physical substances and fluids. There are evidences even within the bounds of the Vedanta philosophy that this abrupt separation between the two orders of knowledge did not always satisfy. Sankara himself, as we shall immediately see, did not persistently maintain what Prof. Radhakrishnan has described as his ‘ultra-philosophicalmoods 5 . Ever and again he turned his thoughts back again to the con¬ sideration of the multiplicity of the world. The philosophy of Ramanuja is, of course, based upon a denial of this separation. 121 THE TWO ORDERS OF KNOWLEDGE And surely it remains true that we can best preserve what is valuable in the doctrine of higher knowledge by showing that such knowledge is the completion and not the negation of lower knowledge. It ought to signify simply the wider conclusions in which the contradictions of the empirical are resolved. Intui¬ tion is the supplement of intellect and fills up what is lacking in the somewhat unsatisfactory conclusions of the latter. Reality is reached, not by turning away from experience, but by fuller and more reverent study of the facts with which it supplies us, just as in ethical endeavour the ideal is approached through the f ulfilm ent, of ordinary duties. There is much truth in Prof. Bertrand Russell’s saying that ‘in contemplation we start from the not-Self, and through its greatness the boundaries of the Self are enlarged’ (.Problems of Philosophy , 246). Even the sym¬ bols of imagination and worship are not to be taken as pure fiction or as meaningless, but rather as more or less valuable hints of truth. The distinction which we have been considering serves us best if we allow it to deepen our reverence, but not to increase our distrust of our own powers. We should like to take it as ultimately expressive of the spirit of the beautiful passage in which Coleridge tells us that all knowledge begins and ends with wonder, but we have to replace the first wonder, which is the child of ignorance, by the larger wonder which is the parent of adoration. 1 In our next chapter we shall have to deal with some of the mediating conceptions by means of which Sankara and other Vedantins strive to soften the rigours of their negations and introduce some definiteness into the vagueness of their abstrac¬ tions. But this chapter may appropriately close with some further reference to Sankara’s views as to the efficacy of works in introducing us to the higher knowledge. We have touched slightly upon this topic in connexion with the preliminary con¬ ditions of philosophic study, but something may be gained by bringing it into relation with the nature of the knowledge in which deliverance consists, and especially its detachment from the lower kind of knowledge. Sankara’s position is that, by the very nature of the case, works, seeing that they belong to that 1 Quoted in Religions of the Empire, 412. 122 THE ULTIMATE UNITY sphere of experience which has to be transcended, can have very little direct efficacy in the securing of our salvation. As he puts it in his Commentary on the first of the Sutras : ‘The know¬ ledge of active religious duty has for its fruit transitory felicity, and that again depends on the performance of religious acts. The inquiry into Brahman on the other hand, has for its fruit eternal bliss, and does not depend on the performance of any act.’ 1 The whole conception of activity, as ordinarily under¬ stood, is alien to the sphere of the higher knowledge. Action has to do with what has not yet come into existence, whereas knowledge, and especially the knowledge of Brahman, has to do with something already existent. It is concerned, not with that which is to be, but with that which eternally is. Works have their relation to the transmigratory sphere, where the category of cause and effect is applicable. Further, on the subjective side, it is exceedingly difficult to dissociate from ritual works, and indeed from works of any kind, the idea of merit, which moves through the degrees of more or less, tending now in the direction of pleasure and now in that of pain, and alternating between the moods of hope and fear. But there is no place for such degrees in association with the kind of knowledge which brings release. Inasmuch as it is the knowledge of that which in itself is not susceptible of increase of decrease, the knowledge also is either there or not there. It is immediate, and it is wholly inappropriate to regard it as the gradual acquisition of repeated endeavour. Moreover, every action is a finite cause which can have only a finite and, therefore, temporary, effect; but, on the other hand, ‘that release is something eternal, is acknowledged by whoever admits it at all, and the teaching concerning Brah¬ man can therefore not be merely supplementary to actions.’ 3 Nor is the case for action improved, according to Sankara, if we take it in its purely intellectual aspect, and argue that, be¬ cause release is the result of action, therefore it must involve mental activity. To such a contention Sankara would reply that the knowledge which is active belongs to that lower order in which the object is still distinguished from the subject. We are active in knowledge, according to Sankara, only when we dis¬ regard his fundamental warning and attempt to treat the Self * S.B.E. XXXIV. ii. * S. B. E. XXXIV. 29. THE PLACE OF WORKS 123 as an Object. We should rather fall back upon that form of realization which is deeper than active knowledge, and which follows the spirit of the Kena Upanishad II. 3, where it is said, ‘By whom it is not thought, by him it is thought, by whom it is thought, he does not know it; unknown by those who know it, it is known by those who do not know it.’ Such contemplation as is here indicated, is certainly not active in the ordinary sense, although we must not rule out the possibility of its implying a transcendental activity in the form of intense concentration, aliveness, or awareness. But even if, returning to the practical sphere, we confine our attention to action of the highest moral character, we cannot say, according to Sankara, that releasing knowledge results from this. The Self which even the most elevated action serves to purify, is only the empirical Self, whereas the Self which we wish to attain in the consummation of salvation, is the un¬ changeable Self, which can only be realized, and cannot be im¬ proved by the addition of good qualities or the removal of defects. Action of even the highest kind is meant to alter the soul, and the Self cannot be altered. Further, although we may be aware of the binding and individualizing effect of many actions, and, because of this awareness, may seek deliverance by emphasizing actions of social tendency, even this will not be sufficient. Actions of service and sacrifice certainly loosen the bonds of the merely selfish Self, and may derive their inspiration from a consciousness of the identity of the Self in us with the Self in other men, but they will lead to deliverance only by extension of the Self, whereas what we seek is that deliverance which depends on greater intensiveness—on deepening rather than broadening. We may unite ourselves more closely with our fellows, we may perfect our relations with them in every respect, and as a result may go far towards founding a kingdom of God upon earth, but such a kingdom will still be only earthly, and our connexion with it will still be a bondage of the spirit. We may become perfect instruments for the good of the com¬ munity, but we shall be instruments still. And we as children of the eternal cannot work with whole-hearted enthusiasm for ends which are constituted even by ideal social relationship. Such conceptions of a perfect society, it must be remembered, 124 the ultimate unity vary from age to age and are different in every nation, and there¬ fore, even a complete identification with the ideals of a particular age or a particular society cannot give us eternal release, based upon absolutely universal conditions. Such, in general, is Sankara’s position as regards the fruit of works. ‘Knowledge, having once spmng up, requires no help towards the accomplishment of its fruit.’ But we should be doing an injustice to his school of thought if we did not point out that he assigns at least a subordinate value to works. Indeed the very sentence from which we have just quoted concludes with the words, ‘but it does stand in need of something else with a view to its own origination .’ 1 It is only selfish works which are entirely useless; all other works may be regarded as indirectly, though not directly, serviceable for salvation. They purify the mind, they strengthen our control of the passions, they induce that calmness and collectedness which are the neces¬ sary conditions of the vision of the true Self. They are, in short, as has been pointed out, ascetic rather than meritorious in their effect. They may remove the hindrances which stand in the way of perfect knowledge, that knowledge which is alone efficacious. Even if they cannot secure the origination of this knowledge in anyone particular life, they may so assemble condi¬ tions that it will of necessity arise in an immediately subsequent life. But, notwithstanding all these concessions, it must be clearly understood, according to Sankara, that, whatever may be the subordinate value of works, they are never to be regarded as ends in themselves. If they are so regarded, bondage either for the individual or the community will be the inevitable result. In his Commentaries on some of the Upanishads, Sankara speaks of four stages in the life of man. With the first, which is under the rule of lawless impulse, and with the second, which is constituted by unintelligent observance of ritual, he concerns himself little. The third stage, however, unites knowledge and works of a higher order, and it may be said that Sankara’s chief endeavour is to show that the combination is not absolutely necessary, and that knowledge alone may be sufficient. When works have been performed so as to secure the purification of the soul, there is no further need of them. As he says in his 1 S. B. E. XXXVIII. 317. THE PLACE OF WORKS 125 Commentary on Sutra III. 4. 14, ‘To a man who knows, no work will cling, should he perform works during his whole life even, owing to the power of knowledge. And this clearly glorifies knowledge/ 1 Co-operation between jnana and karma is necessary only as a preparatory discipline, and the enlightened man will be free from the fetters of both good and evil works. The moralistic standpoint will be altogether transcended. The point of view is in striking contrast to that which, e.g., is ex¬ pressed by Solovyof, who says, ‘Asceticism in itself is not necessarily good, and cannot therefore be the supreme or abso¬ lute principle of morality. The true (the moral) ascetic acquires control over the flesh, not simply for the sake of increasing the power of the spirit, but for furthering the realization of the good/ 2 But with Sankara both good and evil works disappear when the true knowledge arises. He would have been content with the first statement of the Brihadaranyaka Upanishad that ‘all who worship what is not knowledge enter into blind darkness 5 , and if his attention had been directed to the succeeding phrase, ‘Those who delight in knowledge enter, as it were, into greater darkness, 5 he would have immediately replied, as we have seen above, that the knowledge which is here referred to, is the lower knowledge only, and that the passage taken as a whole gives no suggestion of disparagement of the true knowledge which is all-sufficient in itself. Salvation is of faith through knowledge, or is the result of that knowledge whose similarity to faith we indicate by calling it intuition. With St. Paul he would have held that the doing of the works of the law cannot bring salva¬ tion, but, as Deussen points out, Sankara did not hold that the law could not be fulfilled, but rather that, granted its fulfilment, it would even then be fulfilled only from egoistic motives and would therefore be void of effect in the direction of release. He would hardly have agreed with Prof. B. K. Shastri that ‘a simultaneous training in duties and devotion qualifies a man for absolute concentration on the Supreme Soul which leads directly to eternal self-realization or liberation 5 . 3 The question whether this lands us in an antinomian position 1 S. B. E. XXXVII. 294. 3 Solovyof, The Justification of the Good , 57. 3 B. K. Shastri, 77. 126 THE ULTIMATE UNITY will be further considered when we come to treat of the ethical effect of the Vedanta, but in the meantime it may be sufficient to point out that an unqualified imputation of antinomianism would be unjust. In the first place, while Sankara indeed de¬ precates activity, it must be recognized that his ultimate know¬ ledge is of such a character as to contain within itself an activity of a higher order, not the progressive activity of ordinary works or even of ordinary knowledge, but of intense concentration and awareness. It has, moreover, to be repeated again and again, as Sankara brings out very explicitly in his Commentary on Sutra IV. i. i. 1 In the second place, while the enlightened sage may ‘live as he pleases’, and good and evil works are theoretically equally indifferent to him, there may be in this a suggestion that he is above the moral law, not in the sense that he may despise it, but in the sense that he has absorbed it into himself, has overcome its externality, and fulfils it in that spirit of artistic carelessness which is really the highest carefulness. But whether this inter¬ pretation of the sage’s attitude is admitted or not, it is hardly to be thought that one who has realized the value of good works as a necessary propaedeutic, will not continue practically a preference for them over evil works. He will surely still feel, at least in his less stringently philosophical moods, that the health of his soul in its highest spiritual realization is not altogether dissociated from the continuing performance of these good works. From an ethical point of view, as we shall see more fully later, the most serious consequence of Sankara’s position is connected with his depreciation of the enduring value of works of social service and self-sacrifice. A certain want of enthusiasm at least for such works would seem to be inseparable from his general theoretical position. Ultimately, he regards them as forging new fetters, and he seems to be unable to accept the view that while not ends in themselves, they may be ends for the Kingdom of God. Because he has so completely detached earth from God, he cannot make use of a conception of the kingdom of God upon earth. Deussen seems to think that this is a matter of little consequence. He says, ‘Whether this meta- 1 Cf. S. B. E. XXXVIII. 332. THE PLACE OF WORKS 127 physical consciousness, which lifts us above the world . . . leads over into Quietism ... or is realized in deeds of love, touches only its form of appearance and establishes no difference in the value of what appears here/ 1 There does seem to us to be a most important difference in value, and in place of accepting this transcendental equalization and indifference, we prefer to draw attention, as Prof. Tattva- bhushan does, to a concession which Sankara himself is inclined to make. In his Commentary on the eleventh verse of the second chapter of the Gita, he allows that the performance of duties for the good of the world by Sri Krishna and others was not incompatible with even the highest knowledge. 2 We are inclined to think that such an admission may be symbolic of a feeling that the world of ordinary duties and service, temporal though it may be, is not ultimately to be completely detached from the eternal reality. We shall find that such a feeling finds fuller expression in Sankara’s doctrine of Maya to which we must now turn. 1 Deussen, S. V. 424. 3 Cf. Tattvabhushan in Three Great Acharyas, 101. THE DOCTRINE OF MAY A AND AVIDYA . RELA¬ TION TO KANT. THE GOD OF QUALITIES ‘HpHE eye reaches it not, speech reaches it not, thought -U- reaches it not—from the dim and mysterious distance which this verse suggests how can we return to a realistic inter¬ pretation of that world of ordinary experience with which after all we have to concern ourselves ? This is the difficulty which constantly presents itself to all students of the Vedanta and in¬ deed of Indian philosophy generally, and it was a difficulty of which Sankara himself was ever and again poignantly aware. Under his guidance we may have floated upwards from the lower knowledge to the higher, we may have reached that mystical union with the characterless Absolute which he indi¬ cates as the goal of all our philosophical and religious searching, and which constitutes our salvation, but under the pressure of experience we have to come back again to that world from which we have so painfully detached ourselves and which we still find cannot be left out of consideration. As Deussen says, 'We demand from the philosopher as from the empiric investigator, a full interest in the visible world and its wonderful phenomena, only that he must see them with other eyes than the empiric/ 1 That Sankara himself is aware of the insistence of such a demand is obvious from his placing the two orders of knowledge side by side and from his giving at least subordinate recognition to the lower; and, though his interest in the wonderful pheno¬ mena of nature and humanity cannot be called ‘full’, he is at least not prepared to leave the empirical world suspended un¬ certainly in the philosophic void. He relies for connexion and explanation on the term Maya with all the implications of this elusive conception. Maya is the m ysterious power which, through undefinable assodiaSdirwitE ffie~Absolute, turns the non-qualitative Brah man into the qualitative^ manifested, is ffansfor^ ai|'ocean of auspicious qualities’. From one point of view these Equalities are 'limiting adjuncts’ (upadhis), but from another point of view they are the seminal forces of 1 Deussen. S. V. 81. DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA 129 the universe. Brahman, as qualitative, is the sum-total of the upadhis , and the world of nature and human spirits is their manifestation, and constitutes the body of Brahman and the concrete revelation of his being. Mdyd is the principle of indi¬ viduation and the fullest explanation we can give of the visible universe in all the variety of its ‘names and forms’ and the opportunities it presents for the existence and responsible activities of mankind. We may notice two particular directions of the activity of Mdyd. Through the power of envelopment (dvarana) it pro¬ duces the idea of individualized Self-hood, and through the power of projection (viksepa) it produces all the phenomena of the external world. Or, as it has been put, ignorance has both The power of obstruction by which it hides from our view the real nature of things, and the power of development by which it gives to airy nothing a habitation and a name’. 1 Another Indian writer avails himself usefully of the conception of ‘polarization’. ‘Mdyd is the divine power which manifests itself in various ways, but the nature of its operation has this constant characteristic that it brings about diversity (bheda) out of unity (abheda); the opposition which it sets up between the subject and the object may be compared to the action of a mag¬ netic force which- lets off opposite kinds of magnetism at the two poles of a magnet.’ * And yet, even if we are to admit the existence of mdyd, we must, according to Sankara, hold firmly to the contrast between it and the absolute Source from which it springs—to the con¬ trast between the non-qualitative and the qualitative, the infinite and the finite, the changeless and the changing, the imperish¬ able and the perishable, the invisible and the visible, the unity and the manifold. If we indeed permit ourselves to turn towards the world of experience, we must always remember that our steps are leading us downwards. We may seek to know the world in which we live ; but after all, for the sake of this knowledge, we have to leave behind-—and sacrifice—the incog¬ nizable Reality; and that which cannot be known through the ordinary forms of cognition^emains the ultimate foundation of 1 Pundit K. N. Tarkabagisa. * P. N. Sen, Philosophy of the Vedanta , 116. K I 3 0 DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYl all things. Thus a sense of depreciation attends us even as we set out upon our quest for a solution of the problems of the world. This sense may lie hidden in that interpretation which is so often given to the conception of maya> by which it is taken to be the equivalent of ‘illusion 5 . We consider that it is entirely wrong to accept this interpretation in a crude and literal sense, and without some kind of qualification. There is a wealth of signifi¬ cance in the conception of maya which the English word ‘illusion 5 does not by any means fully express, and the precise degree of suitability which attaches to the translation requires considerable investigation. But before we undertake any critical analysis we may trace the growth of the maya. conception itself and indicate generally Sankara’s own use of the term. In the earliest usage, as far back as the Rigveda , the root idea associated with the term would seem to be the wonderful power of the gods, through the operation of which they display a wisdom far transcending our ordinary experience or faculties of comprehension. But with the idea of the wonderful the idea of the mysterious is combined, and by a further not unnatural transition of thought, the idea of the mysterious may be trans¬ formed into the idea of the deceptive. In our attempts to grasp what is beyond the reach of our faculties, we inevitably make mistakes; but mistakes for which we are not willing to shoulder the responsibility, come to be regarded as attempts on the part of others to deceive us. Our inability to apprehend the gods adequately has as its natural counterpart an intention on the part of the gods to mislead us. And we entertain this slightly malign idea of deception all the more easily if, as was the case in Rigvedic times, religious belief attaches itself to two sets of gods, one of which is benevolent and the other malevolent. A mysterious supernatural power the exercise of which is con¬ ceivably beneficent is ascribed to the good gods, whereas the mistakes which we make and the practical blunders which work our misery are ascribed to the evil gods, and appear as maleficent powers belonging to the latter. A firm association thus grows up between the idea of divine power and the idea of deception, and when once the association is formed it is not easily broken. 1 1 Cf. P, D. Shastri, io and Happel, Grundanschauung der Inder , 88. DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA 131 In fact as the idea of mystery deepens and terror darkens the originally familiar relations between men and gods in Rigvedic times, new scope is found for the working of the idea of decep¬ tion, inasmuch as what a man fears he hates, and what he hates he is inclined to interpret malevolently. Hence, when the idea of the supernatural is so strongly emphasized as it is in the latest of the Vedas—the Atharvaveda —it is not by any means sur¬ prising that the idea of magic or deceptive illusion should become increasingly prevalent: We shall find that all attempts to describe the character of mayd have to face the difficulty of deciding whether it is to be regarded as Being or non-Being, sat or asat. The implications of this alternative will require later treatment, but in the mean¬ time we may use the contrast as an indication of the course of historical development. From the ordinary naive point of view the actual is the real—everything else is asat, mysterious, un¬ real, uncanny. But as the sense of mystery deepens, and philo¬ sophical interest develops and becomes more penetrating, the supersensible acquires greater importance than the sensible. The former becomes the real—the truly real—and the facts and events of ordinary experience become attenuated into the veils which hide reality from us. They in turn are now the asat, the dreamlike, the fictitious, constituting the world of appearance, almost the realm of illusion. The philosopher has indeed come to £ see with other eyes than the empiric 5 , and what the latter calls sat , he calls asat , The fluidity of the distinction between the real and the unreal, and the interchange of characters, recalls the definition in the Platonic philosophy of opinion, which has been described as 'something lying between the purely existent and the absolutely non-existent—something more dusky than knowledge, but more luminous than ignorance 5 . 1 - Our present purpose does not require us to trace the his¬ torical process in further detail. Sankara, it has been pointed out, does not obtain much support for a rigorous doctrine of maya from the Vedanta Sutras, and, in reference to their sources in the Upanishads, there is a good deal to be said for the conten¬ tion of Colebrooke, Cowell, and Dr. Barnett, that these favour . 1 For an excellent description of the relation between sat and asat, cf. Kirtikar, Studies in Vedanta, 191. i 3 2 DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA a realistic interpretation of the universe and that the maya doc¬ trine is not to be found explicitly in them. Yet, on the other hand, it cannot be gainsaid that there are implicit suggestions of the doctrine from the very beginning of the Upanishad development. Deussen regards the conception as being the necessary complement of the doctrine of the sole reality of the Atman, which, according to him, is the fundamental teaching of even the oldest Upanishads; and it may be argued that Sankara gives on the whole the true interpretation of the ulti¬ mate position taken up by the Upanishads in face of the diffi¬ culties of reconciling the manifold unity and the finite with the infinite. To Sankara’s own position we must now turn. He certainly does not, in his language at least, guard with any great care against an extreme illusory interpretation. In his Commentary on Sutra I. 3. 19 he tells us that the one highest Lord 'manifests himself in various ways, just as a thaumaturge appears in different shapes by means of his magical power’. 1 In I. 4. 3 he asserts plainly that the causal potentiality ‘is of the nature of an illusion’. 2 And the entire effect of this potentiality is ‘a figment of nescience’, and the ‘germs of the entire expanse of the phenomenal world are the result of illusion’. 3 Still more emphatic is he in his Commentary on II. 1. 23, ‘This entire apparent world, in which good and evil actions are done, is a mere illusion, and does in reality exist not at all’. 4 Also in the retractation of the world which he has evolved, the supreme Lord preserves the detachment and indifference of the magician. All effects, according to the Vedantic view, are but illusory appearances of the cause. .The changes which attract our notice are but vivartavada changes, and not parinamavada, the former term indicating a less degree of actual effectuation than the latter. According to Sir R. G. Bhandarkar, ‘the former implies an illusive development and the latter real development.’ 3 Sankara combines this idea of vivartavada changes with the doctrine, repeatedly stated by him, that cause and effect are identical, and, when confronted with the objection that, if this is so, the cause will be affected by the evils and defects of the world, he cites first of all the analogy of the clay remaining B. E. XXXIV. 190. 3 lb. 243 3 Cf. Sutra II. 1. 14. 4 S.B.E. XXXIV. 345. 5 Vaishnavism , 160, DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA 133 unaffected finally by the form of the particular vessels made out of it, but bases his main defence upon the contention that the evolution has not after all been real. His conclusion upon the question is that just ‘as the magician is not affected at any time by the magical illusion produced by himself, because it is unreal, so the highest Self is not affected by the world-illusion’. 1 Such passages would certainly seem to support very strongly the interpretation of illusion, and many writers accept this meaning unhesitatingly and without qualification. Usually it is against non-Indian writers that the charge of precipitancy in this respect is brought, but some Indian writers are equally ready to accept this view. Prof. Prabhu Dutt Shastri, e.g., says, Tt is true beyond doubt that Sankara means by Maya nothing but illusion.’* And Prof. S. N. Das Gupta is of much the same opinion, Tn Sankara the word Maya is used in the sense of illusion, both as a principle of creation, as a sakti (power) or accessory cause, and as the phenomenal creation itself, as the illusion of world-app earance. ’ 3 ! The impression of detachment from all effects of the magical power is strengthened when we take into consideration the motive which is ascribed to the highest Lord in the creation of e cosmic illusion. This is a corollary of the accepted doctrine of salvation; for if salvation is to consist in a realization of the ephemeral character of the world rather than in submission to a rigid system of inexorable laws, then it is obvious that a similar freedom and light-heartedness must be attributed to the Lord who exercises the magical power. There must be, as Max Muller points out, a considerable degree of self-forgetfulness. 4 The Creator cannot be conceived of as labouring from a sense of need or for the accomplishment of any serious purpose. He needs nothing, he aims at nothing. J Rather is he like the child of sportive impulse, blowing bubbles lovely as the rainbow but no more lasting. Or he is like a mighty prince of satiated desire, who yet must find some amusement to relieve the tedium of the passing hour.| Now at first sight this might seem to be a wholly frivolous conception, and it has, as such, been subjected to much hostile * S, B . E. XXXIV. 312. 3 Das Gupta, I. 470. 3 P. D. Shastri, 26. 4 Cf. Muller, S. S. 185. i 3 4 DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA criticism. But we venture to think that a good deal of this criticism is undeserved. The conception may be wanting in depth, and it may be allowed that it would only be possible for one in whom the tendency to depreciate the world system was already strongly marked. But at the same time it at least hints at ideas of considerable philosophical importance. It may be an attempt to deal in a symbolic way with the difficulty of con¬ necting the idea of purpose with the Absolute, a problem which occupies much space in the writings of Lotze and is one of the most important topics in Prof. Pringle-Pattison’s Idea of God . Further, the thought of play is not far removed from the idea of the exercise of energy without strain, as in the healthful rhythm of breathing, or from the idea of effortless growth towards perfection. 'Consider the lilies of the field, how they grow; they toil not, neither do they spin: and yet I say unto you, that even Solomon in all his glory was not arrayed like one of these/ 1 A recent writer in the Hibbert Journal emphasizes the idea that play is as important as work in the evolutionary process, and urges us to realize the kinship of recreation to creation. 3 An allied idea appears very frequently in the writings of Dr. Rabindranath Tagore, who holds that joy is of the essence of the divine nature and that we should approach more nearly to the secrets of the origin of the world if we would assign greater importance to the idea of creative imagination. In any case, whatever general philosophic import we may assign to it, the idea of Ilia, or ‘sport’, can be rightly estimated only if we take it in connexion with the anti-realistic tendency of Sankara’s whole system. If the conception seems sometimes to work out into a cold indifference to the sufferings of humanity, yet our sense of fitness is not offended to the same extent as in a more realistic system. We might conceive of Sankara as saying in reference to suffering, Tt is not, and therefore does not matter,’ whereas a more realistic thinker would have to say, Tt is, and yet it does not matter.’ A statement such as the following from the more realistically inclined Vedantist, Ramanuja, is much more disconcerting than if it had emanated from a ) 1 Matthew vi. 28. * Art. ‘The Spirit of PlayV by Greville Macdonald, Hibbert Journal, Jan. 1923. DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA 135 thoroughgoing anti-realist like Sankara: ‘To the soul, therefore, which is subject to karman, the connexion with different things is a source of imperfection and suffering; while to the highest Brahman, which is subject to itself only, the same connexion is the source of playful sport.’ 1 But, in order to gain a more complete understanding of the conception of may a, it is necessary to proceed to an analysis of a term which has been left too long out of account, viz. avidya, or Nescience. For the purposes of his refutation of Buddhistic subjectivism Sankara adopted provisionally the ordinary em¬ pirical belief in an external world, but later discarded such a belief, in order to prepare the way for an assertion of the one and only reality. He objected to the Buddhistic view that our experience is independent of external data; but he adopts also the position that the external data are themselves untrustworthy and that unity alone exists. Psychologically, the motive for this procedure of Sankara’s may have been a sense of the inadequacy of our ordinary categories, and in respect of the agnosticism which is implied in the word avidya, Sankara may be legitimately regarded as a precursor of Kant, to whom he is repeatedly com¬ pared by most Indian writers and also by Deussen and Max Muller. But, as the latter also points out, there is a considerable difference between the ultimate view of Sankara and that of Kant . 2 Sankara does not go so far as Kant in the analysis and detailed subjedification of our mental forms and categories, but his final attitude both to these forms and their products is much more negative. At first sight Kant seems, e.g., to take a more subjective view of space than Sankara. With Kant space is a mental form, although, indeed, by reason of its necessity and universality it may approach objectivity. With Sankara, on the other hand, space is objective in an empirical sense—]|he doc¬ trine of its being a nonentity is untenable,’^and ‘substantiality can be established in the case of space’.? But' when we consider the matter further, we find that this ascription of objectivity falls wholly within Sankara’s provisional refutation of Buddhism, and therefore cannot be taken as his ultimate position. Space turns out to be merely a reality within an unreality. Sankara is • S. B. E. XLVIII. 610. * Cf. Muller, S. S. 173. 3 Cf. Sutra II. 2. 24. 136 DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYl more realistic than Kant only provisionally, but much less realistic ultimately. In his attitude to experience taken as a whole Sankara approaches much more nearly to a negative position. Therefore those who adopt the illusory interpretation of Sankara’s teaching—whether they are correct or not in this acceptance—cannot defend it by identifying it with the position of Kant. It is a mistake to state the relation between the two orders of knowledge in the Vedanta philosophy, as interpreted by Sankara, as simply equivalent to the Kantian relation between phenomena and noumena. The phenomenal and the illusory have by no means the same philosophical value, and in using the latter term Sankara says much more than is implied in Kant’s use of the former. In other words, Sankara is not merely agnostic; he is also condemnatory. As regards the results of our use of the categories it would be just to represent Kant as saying, ‘This, though not very much, is the best we can do,’ whereas Sankara would seem to prefer to say, ‘This is the worst we can do,’ or, ‘This is what we should not do at all, if we desire the highest wisdom.’. {According to the latter it is not merely that our knowledge fails but that it does not deserve to succeed, because it is on the wrong lines. Kant again would admit the validity of the intellectual activities which give rise to the cate¬ gories, and would lament only that they do not succeed in un¬ locking the door of the mysteries. Sankara, on the other hand, would be inclined to hold that these activities are wrong in principle and that they do not only fail to unlock the door into the real world, but considerably spoil the lock. Further, Kant, however inconsistent this may be with his strict doctrine tha t causality holds only amongst phenomena, would yet admit tha t things in themselves are the sources of sense-experience even though not revelatory of themselves in these experiences, where¬ as Sankara would urge that there is no distributed reality which could possibly be even the remote cause of sensational experience. Identification on this point, therefore, of the Vedantic with the Kantian philosophy would seem to be to a large extent misleading. It would be interesting to ask whether, if Sankara had written a ‘Critique of Pure Reason’ from his own point of view, he would have left room, as Kant did, for a ‘Critique of Practical Reason’? A consideration of the classical passage in the Com- DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA 137 mentary on Sutra II. 1. 14 would seem to afford material for an affirmative answer. Here Sankara says, £ The entire complex of phenomenal existence is considered as true as long as the know¬ ledge of Brahman being the Self of all has not arisen. . . . As long as true knowledge does not present itself, there is no reason why the ordinary course of secular and religious activity should not hold on undisturbed.’ 1 But while there is a surface similarity here, the fundamental attitudes of the two thinkers are very different from one another. According to Kant, the activities of the practical reason will afford a true access to the deepest reality, whereas, according to Sankara, practical activities in general are purely provisional; they are operations springing from a darkened understanding and should for the most part be disregarded as soon as the light of true knowledge dawns. That this introduces a most important difference in our total attitude to practical activity will be obvious. The distinction is made clear by Solovyof, who points out that,; while mere doubt about objective reality would have no effect "upon moral activity, dogmatic certainty as to non-existence would certainly have such an effect to a very considerable degree. 2 Having thus considered a possible affiliation between San¬ kara’s doctrine of avidya y or nescience, and the Kantian philo¬ sophy, and having seen that the similarity has been greatly overestimated, we may now return to Sankara’s own develop¬ ment of the conception. We have found that ultimately, and perhaps mainly on religious grounds and with a view to the winning of spiritual freedom/he is disposed to assert the un¬ reality of ordinary experience. At the same time in his criticism of Buddhism he has shown his opposition to particularistic subjectivity, or, in other words, his unwillingness to saddle the individual with the whole responsibility for the wrong know¬ ledge in which ignorance consists. An attempt to reconcile the two positions throws considerable light upon the peculiar character of his doctrine of nescience. Although he might not use modern terms, and although our purpose is simply to show the naturalness of the transitions in his thought and we do not attempt to trace in exact details all the windings of his 1 S. B. E. XXXIV. 324. 3 Cf. Solovyof, Justification of the Good, 10. x 3 8 DOCTRINE OF MAyA and avidyA speculation, yet it may be said that Sankara was very evidently aware of what modern psychologists would describe as the results of intersubjective intercourse. He argues provisionally for empirical realism on the grounds of common perception and the impossibility of providing otherwise, or on the principles of Buddhistic individualism, for the practical concerns of life. 1 Although a few Vedantists might approach such Buddhistic individualism, yet, as Prof. S. N. Das Gupta points out, ‘in the normal Vedantic view the objects of the world are existent as phenomena. . . . The objective phenomena in themselves are of course but modifications of ajnana, but still these phenomena of the ajnana are there as the common ground for the experience of all.’ 3 Sankara’s reasoning apparently is that, if we make mis¬ takes, other people make the same mistakes. Our ignorance is a common ignorance, and the cause of it, therefore, must lie somewhere beyond ourselves. But in universalizing our ignor¬ ance we are at the same time going far in the direction of objecti¬ fying it; we are passing from the view of ignorance as an erro¬ neous mental activity to a consideration of the objects presented by that ignorance to us and to others. We thus evade subjective and individual responsibility. We pass from the negation usually implied by the word ‘ignorance’ to the more positive idea of ‘false knowledge’, which again, be it carefully noticed, is not a mere private possession. But the two seemingly incom¬ patible ideas of objectivity and unreliability can be held together in the mind only if a principle of falsification can be posited as the explanation of the false knowledge. Why not therefore, the Vedantist philosopher asks, replace our subjective ignorance by a cosmical ignorance and transform a psychological or epistemo¬ logical principle into a metaphysical one, a disability connected with our human limitations into an ability to create a world ? Let us conceive, urged Sankara, of a world-ignorance as well as of an individual ignorance, and let us regard the world-ignorance as so far positive as to be able to produce a phenomenal world. Dr. Barnett traces the transition as evidenced in the individual soul, ‘With Sankara and the later Vedanta it is a positive, a false light, a constructive illusion.’ 3 Happel puts the matter more 1 Cf. S. B. E. XXXIV. 421 and 428. * Das Gupta, I. 478. 3 Brahma-Knowledge> 39* DOCTRINE OF MlYA AND AVIDYA 139 objectively and universally. ‘The expression avidya, especially if translated as Nescience, conceals the essence of the conception for the negative expression leads us in a wrong direction, as if the word signified something negative and indicated merely defect. This is an error. Avidya is a mighty power, for through it arise the upadhis, from which again come the aggregates of names and forms and the instruments of our activity, and hence also suffering, birth, death, age, sickness, and so on.’ 1 Thus the same principle which is responsible for our subjective ignorance may also be regarded as the explanation of that objective world which we are supposed to know in the state of ignorance. Here Sankara definitely diverges from Kant. The unreliability of empirical knowledge is found to be due not to the inadequacy of human faculties but to ‘the potency of an all-pervading prin¬ ciple of cosmic ignorance’. 3 To suppose a principle of this sort is at once an acknowledgement of inexplicable mystery and a disclaimer of any attempts at explanation. Ignorance is that which because of its very nature cannot be understood. He who would understand avidya has been compared to ‘a man who should rush to see darkness by means of a far-shining torch’. Moreover the idea of ignorance with its implications of mistake and falsification carries our minds by a natural transition to the idea of an illusory world. If there is a definite suggestion of negation or of the unpermitted in the cause, it is much easier to attach a similar suggestion to the product. Thus avidya and maya have the closest possible affinity with each other. Sankara indeed ascribes to avidya very much the same functions as he assigns to maya. Avidya is the cause of the samara, or aggregate of world phenomena. In the Commen¬ tary on Sutra I. 4. 3 the two ideas are combined. The causal potentiality is of the ‘nature of nescience’, and also ‘of the nature of an illusion’. In connexion with Sutra II. 1. 6 he speaks of the ‘fallacious superimpositions of nescience’, and in II. x. 4 he speaks of name and form as ‘the presentations of nescience’, and in II. 1.28 of nature as ‘a mere figment of nescience’. Avidya is almost personified as a principle of creative error. In general the connexion between avidya and maya is so close 1 Happel, Grundanschauung der Inder, 89. a Frazer, Indian Thought, 88. 140 DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA that it is difficult to distinguish between them. Thibaut is inclined to identify them, and we have seen that Prof. Das Gupta’s opinion is that in Sankara maya means both a principle of creation and the result of this creation. 1 Deussen pre¬ fers to regard avidya as the causal principle and maya as the effect. Avidya works by the ascription of upadhis> or ‘limiting adjuncts’, and maya is the resulting totalization of these upadhiSy inclusive of the ideas of a personal God, the world, and individual souls. We find also occasionally a disposition to dis¬ tinguish between avidya and maya on grounds of valuation, the product of the latter being regarded as having a more elevated character than the former. If such views are correct, this just means that avidya has not wholly detached itself from its indi¬ vidual and subjective origin, has not become altogether cosmical. In a later passage Prof. Das Gupta points out that, according to some Vedantists, may a is more distinctively the projective creative force ( viksepa) and thrusts into embodiment the higher attributes, whereas avidya is rather of the nature of a concealing power (avarana), and is responsible for the less worthy attri¬ butes. Further, it is sometimes indicated that the pure intelli¬ gence of the Absolute in relation with maya produces first of all Isvara, or the personal God, whilst in relation with avidya it produces the individual soul. Too much stress, however, must not be laid on these minute distinctions, seeing that the Vedantist writers themselves do not always observe them, and for all prac¬ tical purpose avidya and maya may be taken as simply slightly different ways of describing that mysterious power which pro¬ duces the more or less unreal world of ordinary experience. Before going farther it is important that we should notice exactly what degree of commitment to reality is involved in the objectification of avidya. If, from being a merely epistemo¬ logical concept it is transformed into a metaphysical principle, then its upholders must be ready to accept the consequences of the transformation. They cannot continue to defend the con¬ ception against attack as if it were merely negative. Deussen seems not to have observed this caution when he says that the principle needs no explanation just because it is wholly negative, and Prof. P. D. Shastri seems to fall into the same error in his 1 Op. tit.y p, 470. DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA 141 refutation of the criticisms passed by Ramanuja upon Sankara. But you must choose between the epistemological and the metaphysical treatment. You cannot treat avidyd , or mdyd r as a principle of metaphysical explanation, and then run away from criticism of it on the ground that it is simply the hypostasis of error and has no true positive existence. It would seem to us that Ramanuja is wholly justified in claiming that the concep¬ tion should be treated seriously and that those who use it should not take refuge merely in its inexplicability. It may turn out that they are right as regards its inexplicable character, but they should not at one and the same time confess this inexplicability and yet continue to use it as a metaphysical principle which, just because of its inexplicability, is exempt from criticism. They must do one thing or the other. Their principle is either some¬ thing or nothing. If it is nothing, it cannot be used to explain the world. If it is something, it must be treated as a positive, having sufficient character to stand investigation. Ramanuja’s challenge to the stricter Vedantists seems to be that they cannot be both agnostic and dogmatic. They must choose between the two attitudes, and if they choose the latter they must abide criticism. They must, further, show the relation of mdyd to Brahman, they must resolve the contradiction between the pure unity of the latter and the admission of a world-principle of differentiation within his being. They must adjust the darken¬ ing power of mdyd to the pure self-luminousness of Brahman. They must show how, if cause and effect are, as they say, identical, Brahman, as reality, can be identical with that which is illusory. If, finally, mdyd is real—even to the extent of being used as an explanatory principle—it cannot be wholly sublated by the higher knowledge which Sankara aims at, and therefore the way of salvation prescribed by the rigorous monists turns out to be deceptive. You may be wrong in taking nescience as an explanatory principle rather than as an intellectual attitude. But if you choose the former you must consider also the conse¬ quences. If ajnana is destroyable, it is not real, and if it is real, it is not destroyable. Ramanuja points out that if nescience is a part of the Atman which is Brahman, it cannot be sublated, and adds that ‘knowledge cannot destroy a real thing’. 1 In * Cf. S. B. E. XLVIII. 116. 142 DOCTRINE OF MAY A AND AVIDYA short, the sum and substance of Ramanuja’s criticism is, Let maya abide the question, or let it be abandoned as a meta¬ physical principle. We seem forced to the conclusion that maya cannot abide the question, if it is taken as a pure principle of illusion, giving rise to an altogether fictitious world. Universal illusionism is impos¬ sible. Mr. D. N. Pal in his Sankara the Sublime indeed says, Tt is delusion that produces delusion. It is disease that pro¬ duces disease,’ 1 but Sankara himself would, we think, be ready to point out the fallacy underlying this statement, and would allow that in disease there is a positive maleficent agency at work. In general also he would admit that you cannot hang a chain of illusion in the air, that you must get back to reality somewhere, and that only the real can produce anything, even a power of illusion. The logic of the system would seem to demand an ultimate acceptance of reality. As Prof. Das Gupta puts it, 'With Sankara the forms of the external world were no doubt illusory, but they all had a permanent background in the Brahman which was the only reality behind all mental and physical phenomena.’ 2 Vedantists are fond of the illustration of the rope and the snake, but after all it is an actual rope which produces the illusion of the snake. Sankara himself says, ' When¬ ever we deny something unreal, we do so with reference to something real; the unreal snake, e.g., is negatived with refer¬ ence to the real rope .’3 It may be said indeed that a rigorous illusionist has no right to the word 'illusion’: he ought to confine himself to the word ‘hallucination’, for all 'illusion’ involves an ultimate reference to reality such as we have just indicated, and what is true of a particular illusion is true also of the cosmic illusion. An Indian writer, St. Arulnandi, puts it thus, 'If you say that all knowledge is Illusion, what you call Brahman is Illusion; and, if Brahman is illusion, the assumption of intelli¬ gence falls to the ground.’ 4 Such reasoning would seem to be incontrovertible: somewhere we must rest in the serie? of nega¬ tions. The question comes to be, how far back are we to go in our search for reliable reality? Are we never to call a halt until 1 Op. cit. 198. * Das Gupta, I. 168. 3 Com. on Sutra 111. 2. 22, S. B. E. XXXVIII. 168. 4 Quoted in Carpenter, Theism in Medieval India, 361. DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA 143 we have reached a Brahman without qualities and, in our back¬ ward look, are we to negate entirely the world from which we have started—sweep it out of existence with the magic word 'illusion’ ? Here we come to the centre of our problem. What was it that Sankara did? Was he a thoroughgoing illusionist? Did he escape from every problem through what Carpenter calls 'the backdoor of illusion’? What is the final interpretation of this concept ? Is all that we see or seem But a dream within a dream? 1 We have seen that some of Sankara’s fellow countrymen have taken the conception at its face value, and that he himself fre¬ quently uses language which would suggest that he was inclined to flee from the contradictions of the world and take refuge in the conception of universal negation. But such a view would not, we consider, represent the fullness of his thought, and there is much to be said for those who attempt to present the matter in another light, even though at times their conclusions may seem to go beyond the evidence. The first line of defence is that the whole conception of maya is simply a symbol of humble and reverent agnosticism. As Swami Vivekananda puts it, Sankara was content through this conception to give us 'simply a statement of the fact of this universe, of how it is going on’. 2 It is argued that, like a Scottish philosopher of later days, Sankara felt that 'his line was too short for such vast abysses’. When confronted with the prob¬ lem of the multiplicity of things, he, like Lotze, could not see 'how a plurality ever arose out of a single principle unless various conditions . . . constrained it to produce here a and there b or c \ 3 The conception of maya was the sign and sum¬ mary of Sankara’s perplexities. The multitudinous things of the world were all a problem and a perplexity. They were and yet they ought not to be; for they were inexplicable. As Prof. Radhakrishnan puts it in attempting to express the attitude of Sankara, 'As for the empirical ramifications which also exist, well, they are there, and there is an end of it. We do not know 1 E. A. Poe,‘The Sleeper.’ * Jnana- Yoga, 10. 3 Philosophy of Religion, iB. 144 DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA how and cannot know why. It is all a contradiction and yet is actual. 51 Maya was the conception chosen to indicate the inexplicable. But, as we have seen, when that which is inexplicable or inde¬ finable is set over against an abstract unitary being, a deprecia¬ tory attitude is apt to emerge in reference to the inexplicable. The indefinable is of lesser worth than the definable; it is some¬ thing which cannot obviously be connected with the one great Being; which, in other words, ought not to be, and is therefore ultimately dismissible. So maya was made to bear the burden of the mystery, and the conception was itself invested with contradictions, of which perhaps the most important was that it could be said, not at all without meaning, both to be and not to be. And further degradation still was inevitable. From the idea of depreciation to the idea of deception is but a short dis¬ tance, for when impatience of the inexplicable manifests itself, the inexplicable is soon transformed into the delusive. We cannot hold that whatever is a mystery to us is inexplicable also to God. But for God to cause what is plain to himself to become misleading as far as we are concerned, is to put into operation a principle of concealment and deception. In this way Sankara’s perplexity led him to the very edge of the morass of illusionism, although originally and in deepest intention he was a humble agnostic, worthy to have ascribed to him in the words of Prof. Radhakrishnan, ‘a touching humility bom of intellec¬ tual strength,’ 2 of which humility and which strength maya is the appropriate expression. This agnostic implication of maya is emphasized by many writers.. Dr. Rabindranath Tagore says, * The word maya is a mere name, it is no explanation, 5 ^ Prof. Das Gupta describes it as ( a category which baffles the ordinary logical divisions of existence and non-existence and the principle of excluded middle 5 /\and Max Muller points out that the ‘primeval Avidya is left unexplained, it is not to be accounted for, as little as Brahman can be accounted for’.S Further, on the lines of a frequent criticism of the Kantian philosophy, it has been pointed out that we are not justified in raising the question of the cause of Nescience, because causality applies only to that 1 Radhakrishnan, I. 35. 4 Das Gupta, I. 442. 3 Op. cit. 34. 3 Sadhana , 95. 5 Muller, S.S. 171. DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AV 1 DYA 145 empirical world which in its totality is the result of Nescience, and cannot therefore explain the relation between Nescience and the Absolute or between Nescience and the totality of the world produced by it. As Mr. M. L. Bhattacharya puts it, ‘We are not justified in raising the question, What is the cause of Nescience? as all our ideas of causality fall within the circle of Nescience, and so to find the cause of it would be like mounting upon one's own shoulders.' 1 . Now it is possible that Sankara was to a large extent the reverent agnostic corresponding to the point of view indicated in these passages. It is possible also that a definite advance from agnosticism to dogmatism was left to later thinkers and that Prof. Das Gupta is right when he says that Sankara only made explicit the doctrine of maya in itself and that it was his followers who were responsible for further metaphysical charac¬ terization. 2 But we cannot help feeling that very frequently Sankara himself appears as the negative dogmatist who was not content to say simply that we must leave unsolved the problem of the existence of the many, but went the length of asserting that all plurality must be illusory. The other line of defence is taken by those who adopt the interpretation of the Vedanta philosophy favoured by Ramanuja, and minimize almost to vanishing point the difference between him and Sankara. Ramanuja's position is that Scripture does not teach us that Brahman is devoid of qualities, and that when it is said that he is ‘without a second', all that is meant is to deny the existence of any other principle separate from Brahman. If, on occasion, it is said that he is without qualities, the inten- tion is only to negate undesirable qualities and nothing more. The plurality which is denied is that which would contradict the conception of the world as being in its entirety an effect of Brahman.3 Ramanuja thus sums up his conclusions: ‘The authoritative books do not teach the doctrine of one undiffer¬ enced substance; they do not teach that the universe of things is false; and they do not deny the distinction of intelligent beings, non-intelligent beings and the Lord3 ' 1 Pe /^ ta Phi l 0S °P h y> 55 - * Cf. Das Gupta, I. 470. 3 £ f - s Commentary on Sutra I. 1. 1, S. B. E, XLVIll. 8<. 4 lb. XLVIll. 102. 2 L 146 DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA Now our differing amount of emphasis upon the particu¬ larity of the world may lead us to occupy our minds either with the idea that everything is connected with Brahman, or that there is nothing of value requiring connexion with him. We may mean either that through Brahman all is known, or that there is nothing to be known except Brahman. Those who hold that the positions of Sankara and Ramanuja are very nearly identical in regard to this matter would choose the first inter¬ pretation. If we accept the principle that ‘nothing exists uncon¬ nected with Brahman 5 , we may of course emphasize the first two words, but if we do so, we, in their opinion, misrepresent Sankara in regarding him as an illusionist who denied the reality of the world. His real intention is to lay stress on the connectedness with Brahman of the things of the world and not to assert their unreality. Sankara’s teaching is tha t we are wr ung if w e take the plurality in sepa ration TrornTBrahma n. Xhe thingsoFTKe worldT^urelndeed^unreal in thejiLaeparate partiafi^ with Brahman jthey partake o f his regdity r^Tfare emphasis^wK^ upon the unity and unchangeableness of Brahman is intended to indicate that the world cannot be resolved altogether into par¬ ticulars but is throughout dominated by the controlling con¬ tinuity of the Divine Principle. The ultimate Unity is certainly not to be identified with the variety of the world, but on the other hand it is not exclusive of that variety. In order to reach , an apprehension of the Divine Unity we may indeed have to fSggtFffie^verslfy^ buFthis nep6urTIsmiiy provisioiial^iid_ tEetrc^^ we negate^dSthings, but wKerTwuViSwTiin^ , it is lieI37 IsTin^ in the Vedanta. As Kirtikar ^puts it, ‘The finite world is not lost in the Vedantic Brahman, /but retains its individuality. Even the individual who has 'reached perfection is not lost. 51 From this point of view the Vedanta has been described as a ‘philosophy of relative reality 5 . What is actual has certainly no independent existence, yet it has existence, and is unreal only if we mistakenly ascribe indepen¬ dence to it. We believe that this may properly describe Sankara’s underly- 1 Kirtikar, 108. DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA 147 ing thought and that it was the position at which he was ulti¬ mately aiming. But he can hardly be said to have reached it. If he had done so, he would not have been satisfied with saying that the 'entire complex of phenomenal existence is to be con¬ sidered as true’ only ‘as long as the knowledge of Brahman being the Self of all has not arisen 5 . The truth which he does not seem to have grasped, and which many of his followers also have failed to grasp, was that you cannot teach the essential connectedness of the world with Brahman , and at the same time asserF^ or other tEswhole world must ceaseJto be real. IITFlsTonneHedwith Brahman in its essential charac¬ ter ^JtniugFhay^at least somethm^^ of Brah¬ man. As Thibaut rightt^pomts outTtheli’phoIder of the may a doctrine cannot claim that his doctrine means merely that ‘we are to look upon the whole world as a true manifestation of Brahman, as springing from it, as animated by it. . . . For him it would be appropriate to say, not that everything we see is in Brahman, but rather that everything we see is out of Brahm an, viz. as a false app earance spread over it and hiding it from us. 51 Our conclusion then in regardTio the realistic aspect of may a which has been emphasized by some defenders of Sankara's position, and which has been outlined in the last two or three paragraphs, is that it represents an ideal at which he was aiming rather than a conclusion which he actually reached. He was prevented from any satisfactory realistic rehabilitation of the world by the mystical trend of his mind, which caused him to be more interested in unity than in diversity. While he did not neglect the latter, and indeed devoted a great part of his teaching to cosmological theory, yet he did not treat the matter seriously enough. Instead of patiently studying the world of ordinary experience and arriving gradually at a unifying interpretation of it, he allowed himself to be too easily disconcerted by its insta¬ bility and its confusion, and, impelled by religious devotion expressing itself intellectually in intuition, sought for a way of escape from it rather than for a solution of its problems. Thus he was ready to accept the negative and unsatisfactory concep¬ tion of maya, which, as many even of its defenders allow, is not 1 S. B. E. XXXIV, p. cxx. Cf. also the present writer’s Pantheism and the Value of Life , 227 ff. 148 doctrine of may a and avidyA much more than a confession of the insolubility of the problem. He was also hampered by the abstractness of his thought and by his preoccupation with the idea that the Ultimate must be without qualities. This dominating idea not only made his search a hopeless one, but prevented him from finding in the unity for which he was searching any key to the baffling prob¬ lems of the world. In his conception there stood on the one hand the bare abstract Unity, and on the other the confused world of experience. He could not bridge the gulf—except by the conception of maya> in itself a recognition of the inexplica¬ bility of the world and a depreciation of its value. Still it would be a mistake to regard the conception as wholly a confession of philosophic defeat. It was more than this. It was also a symbolic expression of that mystic consciousness which lies in the depths of religious devotion, and which is content to see the world pass away and the glory thereof, if only it may abide in the Eternal. It is an implicit testimony to the belief that the world is spiritual in its origin and essence. It shows something of the spirit which, in Merejkowski’s novel, The, Death of the Gods, the philosopher Iamblichus seeks to instil into the youthful Julian, ‘Your soul will smile at your body as at a phantasm of the desert. You shall become silence, you shall no more find utterance. And if at that moment the world should crumble away, you would be happy; for what would the world signify to you, since you shall be with him.’ 1 The tendency to negation was stronger in Sankara than the tendency to affirmation, and what was wanting in his philosophy was a fuller conception of God which would have led him to see that to overcome the world both theoretically and practically was better than to flee from it. In the words of Happel, "Not to the destruction of sense or to the loosing of bonds between Spirit and sense is man called, but to the domination and con¬ trol of the latter. He is called to an ever fuller illumination and understanding of sense through the help of the spirit, so that finally the sensible world may no more detach itself from the Spirit, may no longer show itself as may a, but, itself filled with the spirit, may become an eternal instrument of the spirit.’ 3 x Death of the Gods , 86. 2 Happel, 225. THE GOD OF QUALITIES 149 The analysis of the implications of maya leads us naturally to a consideration of the distinction which Sankara makes between the Brahman of qualities and the Brahman without qualities. In conjunction with this we must also take account of the opposite view of Ramanuja, who holds that the distinction is unjustifiable, and a similar view of some of Sankara’s own followers who hold that even in their master’s teaching the distinction, though it may have been made, was not ultimate. The depreciation of the world of ordinary experience which we have seen to be implicit in the conception of maya seems certainly to be reproduced in the distinction, emphasized in Sankara, between the higher or attributeless Brahman {param, nirgunam) and the lower or qualitative Brahman {aparam, sagu- nam). Of the former we can predicate nothing except reality. It is altogether beyond knowledge in the ordinary sense of the term, although it is not unknown to the highest intuition. As the Taittirlya Upanishad says, ‘The words and thoughts turn back from it and find it not.’ 1 In the oscillation of the human mind between the conceptions of sat and asat, Being and non- Being, it always occupies the side of the relationship farthest away from maya ; in other words, when maya is called sat, Brahman is asat, and when maya is asat, Brahman is sat. Brah¬ man is, in Deussen’s phrase, ‘the last unknowable origin of the existent’.* It is not a Being which possesses intelligence as an attribute merely, it is itself pure intelligence or self-luminous- ness. It is thought without any objects, and it can itself never become an object of consciousness. It is essentially independent of all relationships, even though it may enter into them. It is untramelled and infinite, essentially blissful and peaceful in the sense of being free from all influence of variety or change. On the other hand, the sagunam, or lower Brahman, is the abode of all good qualities, and from these qualities come forth the world and the individual spirits. He is Isvara, the personal God, and he gives rise to all beings according to the ordinary cosmological processes of immanental theology. Matter and souls are his modes. They exist in God in a subtle state, un¬ evolved so long as the pralaya stage persists; but when this comes to an end, God, through an act of will, assumes creational 1 II. 4. a Deussen, F. 131. ISO DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA form and expands himself into all the diversity of the empirical world, which diversity again will be resolved into the original being at the end of every age, or kalpa. The question we have to consider is the relation between these two Brahmans. Sankara insists on a distinction between them, and holds that this distinction is based upon the authority of both the Sutras and the Upanishads. Ramanuja, on the other hand, pushes the conception of the qualitative Brahman back until it becomes identified with the ultimate Brahman. He has no use for a non-qualitative Brahman such as Sankara posits, and declares that the distinction is not supported either by the Sutras or the Upanishads. In the passage from which we have already quoted 1 he states explicitly that the Scriptures ‘do not teach the doctrine of one undifferenced substance’. Now we have seen that the Sutras seem to support Rama¬ nuja’s position rather than Sankara’s, but that there is good reason to think that, though some of Sankara’s arguments, as, e.g., those relating to the order of the passages, may be untrust¬ worthy, yet the tendency of the Upanishads is, on the whole, in the direction of an ultimate of abstract or non-qualitative character. At the stage we have reached, however, we are inter¬ ested not so much in the authority which is behind Sankara, as in the philosophical validity of the distinction itself upon which he lays so much stress. In this connexion it is at least note¬ worthy that by far the larger portions of Sankara’s own treatises are concerned with the relations of the sagunam Brahman to the world and to the individual soul. If his belief in the non- qualitative Brahman had been as whole-hearted as he would have us think, why should he have devoted so much attention to the lower Brahman? Of course, in reply to this it may be said that it is quite appropriate that little space in a philo¬ sophical treatise should be devoted to the exposition of a Being who is chiefly revealed in silence, but again the rejoinder is possible that at least the usefulness of what is of the utmost importance should have been adequately set forth, and that, proportionately, what is of lesser importance should not have had so much attention drawn to it. It is also interesting in this connexion to notice that some of " 1 P* *53 * .■ THE GOD OF QUALITIES 151 Sankara’s followers have practically adopted the standpoint of Ramanuja, and have attempted to ascribe it to Sankara himself. They agree that no abrupt contrast should be drawn between the nirgunam and the sagunam Brahman, and they argue that if Sankara himself seems to make hard-and-fast distinctions, this was only with a view to refuting those who showed an inclina¬ tion to lose Brahman in his works, and who failed to appreciate that vast reserve in the nature of Brahman which did not come to expression, and the divine continuity which persisted amidst all the changes of the phenomenal world. If Sankara was apparently depreciatory of the lower Brahman, it was only through fear that, unless emphasis was laid upon the nature of Brahman as he was in himself, the Creator of the world would become merely a diffused divinity, altogether merged in his works. According to Pundit K. Shastri, e.g., it is a mistake to regard Isvara as distinct from Brahman, and Sankara himself did not make this distinction. What he called illusory was not so much the creative act, but the taking of this act and its pro¬ ducts in separation from Brahman. Isvara is the revelation of Brahman, not complete indeed, because Brahman is inexhaus¬ tible, but still a real expression of the ultimate nature of the ultimate God. We should not think first of Brahman and then of a creator, as if they were two separate powers, on differing levels of importance. They are continuous with each other, and we pass from one to the other by an exceedingly natural transition. 1 It is a little difficult to accept this view of Sankara’s teaching. We are afraid that he can hardly be absolved from the charge of attempting, as Lotze would put it, to write a history of the world before creation, and to think of God apart from the creation of the world. He is fascinated by the idea of unity and simplicity, and cannot but conceive of any breach in this unity as being to a certain extent a degradation. Because our intellect has not so thoroughly penetrated into the details with which it is dealing as to be able to present them in proper harmony with each other, because, in other words, the diversity is still discon¬ certing, he prefers to turn his thoughts altogether away from the diversity and fasten them on the unity. The apprehension of 1 Cf. K. Shastri, 19. 152 DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYl this unity gives him a sense of mystic satisfaction, and when he turns back again to the diversity, it appears as something lower, something almost unworthy. He expresses this feeling in the conception of Isvara as -the first product of Nescience, the primal embodiment of the magic power which is somehow or other attached to the Absolute. In thinking of Isvara we may but very slightly loosen our grasp upon the Absolute, our con¬ ceptions may undergo only the very smallest amount of depre¬ ciation, but still there is unmistakably a change. We have taken a step downwards, and we should not attempt to deny it. The idea of the phenomenal, of the unreal, has been introduced into the being of the God of whom we may conceive or whom we may_worship. As Prof. Das Gupta puts it, ‘In the Vedanta system Isvara . . . is but a phenomenal being; he may be better, purer, and much more powerful than we are, but still he is as much phenomenal as any of us.’ 1 We may press further the question why, if Pundit K. Shastri is right as regards the valuational equivalence of Brahman and Isvara, Sankara should so often argue that differences must be negated in order that unity may be preserved. He says, e.g., that ‘one and the same thing cannot in itself be affected by differences and not affected’, and he considers that the only way out of the difficulty is to say that the differences are illusory. Again he tells us that we may ‘now and again for the purposes of worship’ treat Brahman as qualified by distinctions, but we must clearly recognize that this is a provisional permission merely and is, strictly speaking, inconsistent with an appre¬ hension of the highest reality. 3 Finally, we may recall the character of the mood which is fundamental in Sankara’s thought, and which moves him to declare, that he can find satisfaction only in unity and that ‘the passages of Scripture about the negation of all differences have a meaning which leaves nothing more to be wished for ’.3 He comes very near indeed on many occasions to the conception attributed by a recent writer to the believers in the old Greek mysteries; ‘that the world is not God, or at any rate seems to be not God but a thing apart from God, all shivered by its fall from the Divine into a thousand individual fragments, in fine, that the world 1 Das Gu P ta * I- 477 . 2 Cf. 5 . B. E. XXXVIII. 402. 3 lb. 402. THE GOD OF QUALITIES 153 exists at all—that is the primal evil, the original sin, the source of all the sufferings of the world.’ 1 So we come back to the question, whether this conception of the passage from unity to diversity as involving degradation, this determination to place a God of qualities on a lower level than the unqualified Absolute, is a necessary conception. We do not think that it is. We think that Sankara’s attempt to press this distinction proceeds from a distrust of human faculties which is indeed reverent, but is not fully justified. It is closely connected with his other distinction between two orders of knowledge which we found had been pressed too far. The human intellect cannot indeed reach the ultimate, but, in so far as it works sincerely and humbly, its procedure is trust¬ worthy. We must not transform the inexhaustible into the inaccessible; and Sankara himself seems to admit that the intel¬ lect can in some sense reach the Absolute, seeing that he was able to place the two conceptions side by side and compare them. And he should have pointed out more clearly that the intellect is sublimated and not destroyed in intuition. It does not come to a point at which it has to cast away all that it has gained and proceed nakedly on another path. The results of its previous procedure require transformation but do not incur forfeiture in the presence of the Absolute. Sankara’s difficulties arise from the assumption that the ultimate must be simple and that our ideal relationship with it is one of unity rather than of communion. He seemed to think that his deep desire for religious satisfaction could be satisfied only by the apprehension of an undifferenced ground of Being into which he could sink utterly. He felt that, wherever qualities remained, these must so affect our attitude that God will become an object and so will remain for ever distinct from the worshipper. He was dominated by the idea that in order to know God we must be God. But surely this is not a necessary consequence. It is indeed true that only God can know himself completely, but this does not mean that God must absorb us into himself. Neither does it imply that, on our part, there is,no distinction between us and God, and that only a bare relation of identity can express the highest religious attainment. 1 Art. on ‘Orphic Mysteries’, Hibbert Journal) Oct. 1922. 154 DOCTRINE OF MAYA AND AVIDYA We may not have succeeded in bringing all the diversity of our experience as well as ourselves into perfect harmony with God, but it does not follow from this that the harmony can be reached only through a denial of the diversity. The highest unification would surely come through the fullest appreciation of the illimitable qualities of the ultimate Reality, and not from a denial that it has any qualities at all. It would be more satis¬ factory to regard the quest for identity which Sankara pursued so earnestly and reverently, as a regulative ideal, expressive of the humbling consciousness that our unification with the Divine can never at any stage be regarded as complete. However elaborate our conceptions of the nature of God may be, there is always a ‘beyond’ to be reached; and however firmly we may establish relations between the Divine Unity and the cosmic multiplicity, there are always further and more fundamental connexions waiting to be discovered and systematized. But we are not therefore called upon to give up the quest and the endeavour. We are not required to say that the highest descri- bable conception of this unity which we may have reached, is merely a fiction of our imagination or the misleading projection of a cosmic magician, separated from Reality by a gulf which is unbridgeable or can be crossed only by means of the cloud- enveloped constructions of mayd, There is no necessity funda¬ mentally for this separation between Brahman and Is vara, or for regarding the latter as simply the first product of deception. Isvara is surely more than merely ‘the presiding spirit of mayd , the connecting link between the gross creation and the principle that stands above it’. 1 It is because we are looking for the wrong kind of ultimate Reality, for some abstraction that would ‘maintain its identity unaffected’, 3 that we falter in our quest and reach only ultimate fiction instead of ultimate fact. Perhaps we lose our faith in the procedure of the intellect just because, as has been suggested above, we are too purely intellectual. A more active attitude to life would prevent us from being content with abstractions. If we could recover that sense of‘something mysteriously spiritual, not definite, but vaguely animating the world's it might be for us ‘a presage of what our speculations call the ideal infinite 1 B. K. Shastri, 8i. ■* lb. 17. .3 Italics mine. THE GOD OF QUALITIES 155 deity. 1 If we could throw ourselves with all the fullness of our being into the life of the world in its onward and upward surging, we might perhaps gain such a sense of the value of its individual constituents that we should not be willing lightly to deny them, but should desire to see them sublimated, restored, redeemed in God, and would find God to be himself the ulti¬ mate Reality of the Universe, not requiring to be connected, through the illusiveness of may a, with some further abstract and characterless Being. As Prof. Radhakrishnan puts it, ‘The Self in which we are to find ourselves must be shown to be the true life of the whole and not a mere abstraction/ 2 The Gita states for us a more concrete and satisfying conception than is generally to be found in the Vedanta, ‘He is knowledge, its object and its end, seated in the hearts of all... when he (the worshipper) sees that the separate natures of things are seated in one, and issue from it alone, then he attains to Brahma/3 And one of the leaders of modern thought in India definitely departs from an abstract and purely intellectual interpretation of the ancient Indian ideal: ‘To attain the world-consciousness we have to unite our feeling with this all pervasive infinite feeling. In fact the only true human progress is coincident with this widening of the range of feeling. All our poetry, philosophy, science, art, and religion are serving to extend the scope of our conscious¬ ness towards higher and larger spheres/ 4 1 Alexander, Time, Space, and Deity, II. 367. Of. also Pringle-Pattison, Idea of God, 113. * Radhakrishnan, I. 157. 3 Gita, XIII. 17, 30. 4 Rabindranath Tagore, Sadhana, 18. VII THE DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL. THE PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA F ROM the grudging admission of the reality of the world of . ordinary experience, which is the utmost that we can extract from Sankara’s teaching, we may turn to a consideration of the destiny of the individual souls within that world. In our last chapter we saw that Sankara is dominated by the idea of unity, and that a breach in the unity is almost equivalent to a degrada¬ tion. In even thinking of a God of qualities—of Isvara—we have, in Sankara’s opinion, taken a step downwards. Now if this is true in regard to Isvara, it will be all the more true in regard to the infinite diversity of individual souls. The very recognition of them will be a logical inconsistency, a sacri¬ fice of the esoteric to the exoteric. It is evidently with this thought in his mind that Deussen takes the view that all Sankara’s treatment of the individual souls and their relations to God, all his discussions of immortality, all his somewhat hesitating allusions to the doctrine of karma, are of the nature of a compromise between his abstract idealism and an uncom¬ fortably insistent realism. From a strictly monistic point of view a consideration of the individual soul and its ethical progress is but a sojourning in a lower and impermanent world, and any attempt at a proof of immortality is superfluous, because we are already immortal-—in the only sense of the term which Sankara would approve—in virtue of the essential identity be¬ tween us and God. Moreover, even from the exoteric point of view, immortality is a vain expectation, because all things that exist in the region of the empirical are subject to the conditions of time. The soul which has its birth must inevitably cease to be, and forms only an unimportant item in the unending process of physical particulars. So neither from the esoteric side nor from the exoteric taken by themselves can we win assurance, and it is only from a somewhat doubtful combination of idealism and realism that we can derive any doctrine of individual existence and development either in this world or that which is to come. DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL 157 But Deussen’s view of the matter does not seem to be alto¬ gether satisfactory. In the first place, on general philosophical grounds, there does not seem to be sufficient reason for estab¬ lishing such an abrupt dualism between idealism and realism as Deussen thinks to be inevitable. Idealism does not necessarily involve an absolute denial of the empirical and actual. Secondly, just as it is impossible for a man to jump off his own shadow, it is equally impossible for him wholly to deny the particularity of the world in which he finds himself, and we have already found reason to think that Sankara, while ostensibly a rigorous monist, is at times vividly aware of the necessity of reaching some accommodation to the world of experience. He builds more wisely than he knows and provides windows through which he may look out upon actuality, even while formally denying their existence or necessity. About his formal denial of the existence of individual souls there can be no doubt, and we may first set forth his rigidly esoteric position and contrast it with Ramanuja’s. Vedanta Sutra I. 1. 19 speaks of the ‘joining of this (i.e. the individual soul) with that (the Self consisting of bliss) on that being fully known (i.e. in the anandamaya state)’, and Sankara interprets their ‘joining’ as meaning identity and nothing else. His com¬ ment is as follows : ‘If he sees in the Self consisting of bliss even a small difference in the form of non-identification, then he finds no release from the fear of transmigratory existence. But when he by the cognition of absolute identity, finds absolute rest in the Self consisting of bliss, then he is freed from the fear of transmigratory existence.’ 1 The doctrine of identity is stated even more explicitly and more emphatically in the Com¬ mentary on Sutra 1.4. 22. Sankara selects from the Upanishads that figure which best suits his dominant view and compares the origination of souls from the highest Self to the issuing of sparks from a fire. He declares that the differences between the soul and the highest Self are not real but are due to ‘limiting adjuncts’ only. We have to do entirely with ‘names and forms’ and the individual soulyas an embodiment of these, is the pro¬ duct merely of Nescience. In a still more vigorous passage he says, ‘As therefore the individual soul and the highest Self differ « S. B. E. XXXIV. 71- 158 DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL in name only, it being a settled matter that perfect knowledge has for its object the absolute oneness of the two; it is senseless to insist (as some do) on a plurality of Selfs and to maintain that the individual soul is different from the highest Self, and the highest Self from the individual soul. 51 And looking to the future and the question of immortality generally, Sankara takes up the position that the immortality of the individual soul is relative only. It can be expected only by him who is dependent on The power of the lower knowledge’, and has not ‘altogether burned nescience and the other afflictions’.* Ramanuja, on the other hand, following more or less closely the primary interpretation of the Sutras , but remaining at a greater distance from the general tendency of the Upanishads, holds that the individual soul is real; it enjoys a certain amount of freedom even under the conditions of this life, and passes at death through various stages to the world of Brahman where it will exist, not in a state of indistinguishable identity with the Divine, but in a perfected relation of communion. True know¬ ledge will bring about only the destruction of the separatist spirit in word or in deed. Personality will assuredly continue. The ultimate significance of Sutra I. i. 19 is that ‘the highest Brahman . . . is other than the Being called individual soul’, and the contrary opinion is subjected to the vigorous comment, ‘To say that any one is identical with that by obtaining which he enjoys bliss,'would be madness indeed.’3 In regard to the future and especially the point raised in Sutra IV. 2.7, Ramanuja holds that the immortality there indicated is common both to him who knows and to him who does not know, i.e. the im¬ mortality is not merely relative, and perfect knowledge does not destroy individual immortality. Sankara increases the impression of a depreciation of indi¬ viduality by certain particular interpretations which he gives of various Sutras. In regard to Sutra II. 3. 50 4 Sankara has no doubt of the applicability of the symbol of the sun and its reflections. The individual soul has no more reality than that of a flickering reflection on a restless piece of water. It may be 1 S. B. E. XXXIV. 282. ■* Cf. Sutra IV. 2. 7 ;S. B. E. XXXVIII. 370. 3 S. B. E. XLVIII. 237. 4 49 in Ramanuja. DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL 159 noticed, in passing, that Ramanuja takes an entirely different view of this Sutra. What Sankara translates as, £ And the indi¬ vidual soul is a reflection only’ Ramanuja translates, ‘and it is a mere apparent argument 5 , 1 i.e. the unreality which Sankara ascribes to the individual soul Ramanuja attaches to the argu¬ ment by which the unreality of the individual soul is sought to be established. In a slightly earlier Sutra of the same section, we seem to have the unequivocal statement that ‘the soul is a part of the Lord on account of the declarations of differences 5 . Ramanuja takes this literally, but Sankara, after indicating that the most appropriate symbol is that of the fire and its sparks, says that we must interpret the particular Sutra to mean only ‘a part, as it were '. 2 The individual soul cannot really be a part of that which has no parts, and to suppose that it has parts and that therefore the individual souls are real, is the result of the universal illusion. Ramanuja is vigorously of another opinion and brushes aside Sankara’s interpretation with the contemp¬ tuous remark, ‘Truly, if such were the purport of the Veda, what more would the Veda be than the idle talk of a person out of his mind ? 53 A similar tendency is indicated when Sankara, treating matters from the physical point of view, expresses the doctrine of the identity of the soul and God under the symbol of the all- pervadingness of the former. 4 Ramanuja, on the other hand, recognizes that the most appropriate symbol for his doctrine is that the soul should be regarded as of atomic size (anu). This view is supported by the nine Sutras immediately preceding; but Sankara brushes aside the argument of the Sutras by ex¬ plaining that the atomic view therein indicated refers only to the soul when associated with the organ of intelligence ( buddhi ), and therefore belonging only to a lower state. From a psychical point of view, Sankara argues, in connexion with Sutra II. 3.18, that the soul is pure intelligence, i.e. the eternal intelligence of Brahman constitutes the soul’s essen¬ tial nature and leaves no room for difference. On the other -hand Ram anuj a translates the same Sutra as ‘ The Individual 1 S. B. E. XXXVI. 60 and XLVIII. 565. * Cf. S.B. E. XXXVIII. 61 and XLVIII. 561. 3 S. B. E. XLVIII. 562. 4 Cf. Comm, on-'SutraTip 3. 39; B. E. XXXVIII. 42. 160 DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL soul is a knower\ i.e. an individual, active, consciously intelligent subject, having distinction from Brahman, and the Sanskrit term used, according to Thibaut, bears out his view. 1 There seems to be sufficient support, therefore, for the view that on the whole Sankara’s admission of the individual soul is of the nature of a concession. From the highest point of view it is, according to him, identical with, or at least not-different from, Brahman himself. It is only from the empirical point of view that we are temporarily justified in speaking of a plurality of souls. But Sankara’s own treatment of the matter from the empirical point of view is so voluminous and elaborate (though probably he was constrained to this from the amount of attention devoted to the topic in the Sutras themselves) that we cannot afford to regard it as merely concessional and of secondary im¬ portance. And we must also keep in mind in this connexion the contention of many Indian writers that the English words ‘identical’ and £ non-different’ have not the same significance, and that the latter alone is the proper interpretation of l ananya\ a consideration which may at least incline our minds to a more liberal construction of Sankara’s rigorous monism. The individual soul is constituted—or disguised as Sankara would put it—by the upadhis, empirical conditions or limiting adjuncts. Of these the first is the condition of the gross body, which need not detain us, as this is entirely left behind in the migrations of the soul, and all schools of the Vedanta are far removed from materialism. In the conditions which attach to the soul in the existence which persists through innumerable lives, we may distinguish a changing and an unchanging part. The changing part is of vital importance in connexion with the doctrine of karma y and includes those moral consequences which have been passed on from one to another in an infinite series of lives and which to a large extent determine the em¬ pirical destiny of the soul. The unchanging part is the nucleus of the soul and consists (i) of that substratum which may be called the ‘subtle body’ and which is made up of the extremely subtle counterparts of the gross elements. It has a persistence which enables these subtle elements to continue after the death of the gross body. (2) We > Cf. S. B. E. XXXIV, p. xcvii. DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL 161 have the more active aspect of the subtle body, the life-organs or pranas , the vital breaths of the soul. On the conscious level these include the five organs of sense and the five organs of action, co-ordinated by and under the control of the Manas , or central organ of conscious life. But behind these fully conscious aspects of the soul there is posited, with a fine anticipation of more modern doctrines of the unconscious and the sub-con¬ scious, the Prana (in a limited sense) or Mukhya Prdna* the ultimate nucleus of life, both physical and mental in its relation¬ ships, subtly supporting the physical processes of respiration and nutrition and rendering intelligible the act of death, but having vague affiliations also with the mental activities of the soul which are below the level of clear consciousness. Indeed one of the most interesting aspects of the Vedanta philosophy is just such an interplay between physical and psychic conceptions. It seems to be left undecided whether the soul is more closely associated with the Mukhya Prana or with the Manas , and in this hesitation lies much wisdom. An elaborate account is given of the relations of these various organs of the soul in the three states of waking, dreaming, and dreamless sleep, and also of their fate at death, but into the details we need not enter to any extent. We may note only that at death there takes place a process of involution. The soul gathers the organs of sense and action, or at least the functions of these organs, first of all into the Manas . 2 Then the Manas is merged in the Prdna , or breath. The process may be paralleled on the mental side by the retraction from sense-experience which in the lifetime of the individual has taken place during dream sleep and the further concentration which is associated with passing into dreamless sleep. The next stage is more vaguely described. The Prdna is said to merge in heat (tejas) and is also said to merge in the essence of the individual soul . 3 But in both these ways we come near to the idea of the subtle body (indefiniteness here being made to serve the purpose of comprehensiveness). The subtle body is the fine part of the elements, the seed of the body, and constitutes the vehicle by which the continuity of the soul is preserved from one life to 1 Cf. Deussen, S. V, 326. 3 Cf. Sutra IV. 2. 4. M 3 Cf. Sutra IV. 2. 1. 162 DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL another, unaffected by death. It is the elementary metaphysical substratum of the departing soul. 1 With this is closely associated the moral substratum which by reference to past behaviour determines the character of the departing personality and its future destiny. The karma-dsraya is the summing up of past experiences, of impressions and the results of actions. When the soul is about to enter on its new life, the past experience is focused as an innate concentrated disposition which gives a starting-point, differentiating the new life from previous lives. As this concentrated effect of the past cannot properly be in actuality until the existence which is passing away has come to a definite end, it may be regarded as something new, something which was not there before. Some writers therefore in this connexion posit an entity called the apurva? half physical and half spiritual, which is described as ‘either an imperceptible after-state of the deed, or an imper¬ ceptible antecedent state of the result\3 From one point of view the doctrine of apurva might be regarded as an attempt to get away from the externality of the notion that judge¬ ment is passed upon acts alone, and an anticipation of the more modern view that it is passed rather upon character. Only, in connexion with apurva the character is still left as a some¬ what detached entity and is not brought into organic and ethical connexion with the continuing personality of the doer of the action. Sankara himself, however, does not see any necessity for any such mediating conception, and his hesitation is inter¬ esting for the light which it throws upon the character of the tradition which he has inherited, as well as upon his view of the doctrine of karma. Before touching upon this latter doctrine we may take into consideration the varying kinds of destiny to which the com¬ bination of the elemental and the moral substratum leads the soul. Souls may be divided into three classes: according as they have developed within them knowledge (which, according to 1 Cf. Deussen, S. V. 375. 3 Of. Sutra III. 2. 39. 3 Cf. S. B. E. XXXVIII. 182. Cf. also the Vaisesika doctrine of adrishta — the unknown virtue due to dharma —described in Das Gupta, I. 283. Cf. also the well-known Vedic idea of ishtdpiirta, a compound word denoting sacrifices and offerings. In the Rigveda X. 14. 8 it is regarded as something which can be stored up and which will have effect in after-life. Cf. McKenzie, Hindu Ethics, 14. DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL 163 Sankara, is ‘lower’, but according to Ramanuja is the highest attainable); according as they have depended only on ritual and moral works; and, finally, according as they have neglected both knowledge and works. The first go by way of the Gods (the Devaydna) to eternal and ultimately blissful communion with the qualitative Brahman. The second go by the way of the Fathers (the Pitnydna ) to the moon, there to receive the reward of their deeds and of all the previous attainments of their souls, the retribution continuing, in varying degrees of felicity or otherwise, until only a residue is left, which residue will deter¬ mine their future lot upon the earth, and so on and on, until the purification of their souls is so far advanced as to enable them to exchange the path of the Fathers for the path of the Gods. 1 The third class, composed of those who have not sought to acquire merit either by knowledge or by works, go to the ‘third place’ by ‘a path on which they repeatedly return to the exist¬ ence of small animals’.* It must be noticed, however, that the boundaries between the second and the third classes are left comparatively vague, and the idea is frequently brought for¬ ward that the evil-doers may also receive their retribution in some kind of intermediate state, their destination being, not the moon, but the abode of Yama, whence, after ‘suffering there the torments of Yama corresponding to their evil deeds, they again reascend to this world’. 3 The important distinction, therefore, is between the first two classes, between those who are worthy to enter the Path of the Gods and those who are not so worthy. In connexion with this distinction the interesting physiological and mythological detail is supplied that of the hundred and one veins of the heart, the one which leads up to the head is the path by which the depart¬ ing soul of the worthy man goes to the realm of Brahman, 1 What particular class of works make up this residue is doubtful. It is held by some Vedantists that the stronger works receive their recom¬ pense first, i.e, in the intermediate state, whereas the weaker remain with effect sufficient to cause a new birth. Others are satisfied with a purely quanti¬ tative idea of the remaining balance, while others again attempt to make the distinction between ritual and moral works, and hold .that the former are recompensed in the intermediate state and the latter receive their recom¬ pense or retribution in a new birth. Cf. Sutra III. 1.9; S. B, E. XXXV1U. 121. T Cf. Sutra III. x. 17; S. B. £. XXXVIII. 134. 3 Cf. Sutra III. 1. 13; S-B. E. XXXVIII. 122. M 2 x6 4 DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL whereas the less worthy and the unworthy have to go by any of the other numerous modes of exit. From these descriptions we may select two topics as demand¬ ing further consideration: (i) the doctrine of karma as affecting- the individual soul, and (2) the ultimate condition of those who reach the realm of Brahman. We have already referred to the interesting character of Sutra III. 2. 38-41, and the light they throw on the doctrine of karma. We discover, on the one hand, a tendency in the direc¬ tion of regarding the power of the deed in an objective manner, and, on the other hand, towards resolving all power into the hands of God himself. The first tendency implies that those who hold it have, either consciously or unconsciously, served themselves heir to a long tradition in which the conceptions of ishtapurta, rita, dharma (all implying continuing effects of deed or conduct, both ritual and moral), as well as the later concep¬ tion of apurva, have played a conspicuous part, and in the development of which, down to the time of Sankara, Buddhist influence has been strong. For those who think in this way, the fundamental forces of the universe are still animistically or polytheistically conceived, and we are not far from the con¬ ception of God as struggling against some power of fate outside of himself. In relation to the karma conception, the deeds of men have acquired that independent actuality which invests them with an energy differentiated from that of the central powers of the universe. On the other hand, Sankara—and Ramanuja also—wish to centralize all the available power. The actions of human beings do not bring fruit of themselves, either directly or indirectly: it is the Lord who causes this fruit to appear. But if all power is thus vested in God, difficulties immediately arise as to the nature of God and his relations to men. Will he not appear to be oppressively dominating the activity of the individual ? The general answer of the Vedanta to difficulties of this nature is to suggest, not that the Divine control should be regarded as diminished, but that its relation to human activity should be conceived of as indirect and not direct. If God can be placed at one or two removes from man, then he may be defended from the charge of oppression and at least a semblance of freedom DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL 165 may be left to human beings. Thus the action of God may be generalized so that its incidence is not immediately upon the individual action but upon the whole karmic process in which the individual and his action is involved; fatalism can be softened by being universalized, the tyranny of a tyrant being replaced by the stern inexorability of a law-giver or judge. Or recourse may be had to metaphors which mitigate the harshness of compul¬ sion and represent God as a cause of a more occasional character. God’s control may be likened to the rain in relation to the various shrubs. As the rain provides opportunity for their favourable but diversified growth, so does God arrange ‘favour¬ able or unfavourable circumstances for the soul with a view to their former efforts’. We should compare also the commentary on Sutra II. 1. 34, ‘For as Parjanya (the giver of rain) is the common cause of the production of rice, barley, and other plants, while the differences between the various species is due to the various potentialities lying hidden in the respective seeds, so the Lord is the common cause of the creation of gods, men, &c., while the differences between these classes of beings are due to different merit belonging to the individual souls.’ 1 Still, even metaphors of this kind do not carry conviction, and the almost desperate attempt to remove our difficulties as to the freedom of the individual soul, leads in the same section to what seems to be little more than a bare asseveration of a contradic¬ tion. It. is conceded that the soul acts by its own activity, and almost in the same breath the concession is withdrawn. ‘Al¬ though the activity of the soul is not independent, yet the soul does act. The Lord indeed causes it to act, but it acts itself.’ Reasoning of this sort is hardly sufficiently cogent to relieve us of the fatalism of a passage like Kaushltaki Upanishad III. 8, which Sankara quotes with approval. ‘He makes him whom he wishes to lead up from these worlds, do a good deed, and the same makes him whom he wishes to lead down from these worlds, do a bad deed.’ But, putting aside the question of the apportionment of responsibility between Divine and human power, it must be remembered in this connexion that God cannot rightly be charged with pitilessness and arbitrary cruelty. We must * S.B.E. XXX IV. 358 and XXXVIII. 60. 166 DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL remember not only the metaphysical but also the moral aspect of the karmic process. Even though we were to go all the way with the fatalists, even though we were to admit that God provides the all-controlling conditions of each life and acts also in each particular action of the individual soul, yet in the apportionment of happiness or misery he must have regard to the particular place occupied by the individual soul, and will vary the destiny accordingly. Cf. again Sutra II. i. 34, ‘Hence the Lord, being bound by regards, cannot be reproached with inequality of dis¬ pensation and cruelty.’ 1 He cannot begin de novo . He has to observe the existing actualities and the law which emerges in relation to them, even though this law be little better than lex talionis , based on a principle of exact retribution. The tyrant gives place to the judge or at least to the administrator of the law. We were perhaps rash in saying above that the judge in this case was also the lawgiver, for at first sight it might seem as if God’s righteousness were vindicated by putting him under the constraint of a law external to himself, for which he was not responsible. But there are at least indications of the in¬ fluence of the idea—afterwards so strongly emphasized by Lotze—that the law is not external to God but is simply an expression of his own nature. He himself, as would appear to be obvious when stress is laid specially upon the all-pervading causality of God, is said to be primarily responsible for the whole course of the samsara and the empirical destiny of souls. And although he may also retain the power of graciously grant¬ ing deliverance from the samsara through the saving power of knowledge, yet for the most part his responsibility is discharged in a regular manner. Thus, however we may put the matter, the idea of regularity is conspicuous, and God, being under a law of righteousness, either external or his own, may be de¬ fended from any charge of arbitrariness. But this vindication is immediately countered by another difficulty. Sankara’s critics point out that he has simply pushed the problem farther back. God’s action, it is said, may be justified by the suggestion that he has to act with reference to the deserts of former lives, but what about these former lives themselves, what about the first in the series ? At the beginning x Cf. S. B. E. XXXIV, 359- DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL 167 of the transmigratory process, when there could be no accumu¬ lated merit, what justification could there be for unequal crea¬ tion? 1 Sankara meets this objection with the simple bold state¬ ment that the world has no beginning, because, if it had, then God would have to be accused of arbitrariness. Can this carry conviction? It seems to be a barefaced case of circular reason¬ ing. God cannot be accused of arbitrariness because of the existence of the samsara, and the samsara must exist because God cannot be accused of arbitrariness. But it is not wise to bring a charge of fallacious reasoning against a philosopher of Sankara’s quality, and we have the feeling that there is more in his argument than appears on the surface. Is he not struggling with the difficulty of relating the eternal God to the temporal process ? May he not be making an attempt to place God above time, or, at least, to get rid of the somewhat crude idea of God as standing at the beginning of creation, looking forward, and apportioning to each soul its destiny through all succeeding aeons of time ? Has he not got implicitly in his mind the thought that our temporal categories are inadequate for the representa¬ tion of God, and that he is to be conceived of rather as an over¬ shadowing and pervasive Presence than as one who stands be¬ hind us in time far away at the beginning of human destiny and determining it fatalistically for ever more. And yet Sankara, after looking at the difficulties, seems in the last resort to turn away from them, for his final position is that whatever problems may remain, belong after all to an unreal world, the world of names and forms, and therefore may be disregarded. Why should we worry over apparent injustices in the world or in the Divine control of it when the world itself does not exist? We come therefore in general to the conclusion that Sankara does not deal adequately with the karma doctrine. In so far as he accepts it, he does not relieve it of the charges that it treats each life as subject too much to an individualistic destiny, that it is inclined to hypostatize abstractions under the influence of a persisting animism, that in its more universal aspect its ethical level is legal rather than moral, that it rarely rises above the idea of sheer retribution, and that, despite references to divine grace, it does not escape the danger of impersonal and fatalistic ■ Cf. Sutra II. 1. 35; S. B. E. XXXIV. 359- 168 DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL domination over the human life. In so far as he rejects it, he leaves his rejection side by side with his acceptance. He leaves unresolved the dualism which the doctrine suggests as to the relation between God and the world. He does not by trans¬ forming the doctrine bring the world into organic relation with the eternal nature of God, but turns away from the difficulty as from an unreal problem of an unreal world. We must now consider the second point that has been reserved, viz. the ultimate condition of those who reach the realm of Brahman. By overcoming the evil karma of their past and by scrupulous care that they may not accumulate new karma , they may reach this high position. But in doing so, have they reached the ultimate goal, or must they still confess that they have failed to discover the true path of salvation? Which is to be followed—Ramanuja or Sankara—as regards the doctrine of the ultimate destiny of the soul? In the main they agree as to the preliminary stages. It is in connexion with the final stage of all, and the retrospective valuation of the whole process of the soul’s ascent, that the most important differences emerge. Following their common lead we have found that the souls who proceed upwards on the way of the Devayana , after passing through various stages, at length enter into Brahman’s world to abide with him in an eternity of bliss and perfect communion, with participation in all the qualities of Brahman, according to some, or, at least, as Audulomi thinks, with participation in the intelligence of Brahman. In this state they enjoy the fulfilment of all purified desires, and their lordship is unlimited, except in so far as it is restricted by the cosmic, creative, and sustaining powers reserved for Isvara, who, however, also possesses the power to harmonize any incompatible wishes of the pious. There is finality about this state in that it cannot possibly change into anything lower. Tor them verily there is no return to earth life.’ 1 But whether it is final in the sense that it cannot change into anything higher is just the main question at issue between Sankara and Ramanuja. We may put the problem in both a narrower and a broader way. We may ask whether the stage which is regarded as highest by Ramanuja is really final 1 Of. Sutra IV. 4. zz . DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL 169 or n ot? Or we may raise the question of comprehensive evaluation and ask whether there was really any necessity pain¬ fully and gradually to make our way to such a stage at all. In treating the problem in the simpler way we must bear m mind Sankara’s distinction between the lower and higher Brah¬ man, and we may show that his view is that the Brahman with whom the soul enters into perfect communion at Ramanuja s highest stage, is not the higher but the lower Brahman. This lower Brahman will himself be merged in the higher, and there¬ fore the soul which has entered into communion with the former, will also share in the state of perfect indivisibility with the latter. It will not reach unity with God, but will rather dis¬ cover that unity which has never been lost, that oneness without a second, and, as rivers run into the sea and lose their name and form, so will it merge its identity in the undifferenced Absolute The character which it has acquired in the painful and gradual stage of its ethical and karmic ascent will be lost in a purely metaphysical absorption. By treating the question from the broader point of view we may reach much the same conclusion. We must here keep in view primarily Sankara’s distinction between the two orders of knowledge, and also his depreciation of the salvational value of works. By those who follow him in this attitude it is urged that there is little to be gained by passing through the various stages of the upward ascent; for, after all, the consummation which is aimed at by this method will turn out to be the reward of the lower knowledge only. Therefore we may shorten the whole process, or, rather, make it superfluous, by reaching the illu¬ mination of the paravidya, the highest knowledge, the immedi¬ ate consciousness of identity with Brahman, which is possible for us here and now. Such a result is to be obtained by direct meditation, especially concentrated on the formula tat tvarh an, which exercise of the soul may have to be repeated again and again if the full significance does not dawn upon the first hearing. Works may be of use as preparatory and purificatory disciplines, but not as a means of securing the illumination. In fact, the man who has won emancipation, and thus possesses the higher knowledge, is independent not only of evil but also of good works. There is ‘non-clinging and the destruction of I 7 0 DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL earlier and later sins 5 , 1 and, 'Also of the other (i.e. good works) there is in the same way non-clinging; but at death.’ 3 4 Sankara takes the phrase ‘but at death’ to be merely emphatic and to signify ‘especially at death’. Ramanuja takes a modified view and explains the phrase as meaning, ‘Good works which produce results favourable to knowledge and meditation, perish only on the death of the body (not during the life-time of the Devotee ).’3 The sage, according to Sankara, is thus raised above all conditions of mundane existence. Nothing that is outside of Brahman has any power to disturb him, and he has not to wait for the slow temporal processes of improvement in this life and the next. But why, if Sankara’s view is correct, should he have to wait even for the end of this present life? Sankara deals with this difficulty by citing the physical analogy of the potter’s wheel, which continues to revolve even after it has completed its work in moulding a particular vessel. But behind this metaphor there is also the theory—not by any means confined to Sankara’s teaching —that work effects may be divided into three classes: accumu¬ lated ( samchita ); current, in the sense that they have begun to affect the soul (prarabdha); and finally, those due to the activity of the present life (kriyamana). Illumination affects only the first class and the third. Works which belong to the second class, and have already begun to affect the soul, must continue their opera¬ tion until at death their force is exhausted. Some Vedantists dis¬ tinguish two stages even within the condition of illumination, the lower being the condition of the enlightened sage even pre¬ vious to death (jwanmukti)^ and the higher being the complete stage which is reached in freedom from the body (videhamukti).* But in order to accomplish this final merging in Brahman, we do not require, according to Sankara, to imagine at death any semi-angelic flight of the spirit by the Path of the Gods. Time and space no longer exist for the illumined soul when he has reached the point of death. Then, ends the man Upwards in that dread point of intercourse, Nor needs a place, for it returns to Him What Does, what Knows, what Is; three souls, one man. 1 Cf. Sutra IV. i. 13. 3 S. B. E. XLVIII. 724. 3 Sutra IV. 1. 14. 4 Cf. Barnett, Brahma-Knowledge , 52. DESTINY OF THE INDIVIDUAL SOUL 171 Under such conditions how is it possible to speak of a 'depart¬ ing* or ‘going to Brahman’? ‘To what sphere , asks Sahkaia, ‘then belong the scriptural texts about the soul’s going? To the sphere of qualified knowledge, we reply. . . . The reaching of another place is out of the question. Statements about the soul’s going which apply to the lower Brahman are wrongly put in connexion with the higher Brahman. 1 Even if we at¬ tempt to deal with the matter by means of physical analogies, and speak of omnipresence, there is the same want of suitability, for that which is omnipresent cannot pass from one place to another. And as regards timelessness, the soul need not wait upon the slowness of passing through the various stages. It is now, what it eternally has been. So with great earnestness Sankara argues that the proper interpretation of Sutra IV. 2.13 is that the soul ‘does not depart’. This is the plain meaning of Scripture according to him, and those are altogether wrong who try to wrest this meaning and make out that ‘do not depart’ has reference simply to the relation of the pranas to the soul and implies that they abide with it in readiness for a conjunct passing out at the moment of death. We are not called upon to decide whether Sankara is right or not in regard to the inter¬ pretation of this particular text. There can be no doubt what¬ ever about his own view of the matter, which is, that illumina¬ tion may confer a non-temporal and non-spatial emancipation, making the sage independent of cosmical processes and ethical endeavour, and raising him above the slow movement of the kramamukti (or gradual liberation). Like Iamblichus in Merej- kowski’s Death of the Gods, he would ask, ‘Whence comes that beam which falls upon the soul ? I do not know. It comes unawares, and when one least expects it. To search for it is useless. God is not remote from us. One must make ready, with a soul becalmed; and simply wait, as the eyes aw^it (according to the saying of the poet) the rush of the sun from the dark ocean. God does not come, God does not go away; He is revealed, He is, what the Universe is not, the negation of everything that exists. He is nothing, and He is All.’ 2 X Cf. Sutra IV. 3. 14; S. B, E. XXXVIIL 401. 2 Op. cit. } Eng. trans. Si. i 7 1 PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA The topics which have been treated of in the last few para¬ graphs throw considerable light upon the Vedantic view of the relation of ethical endeavour to ultimate reality, and to this question we must devote the remainder of this chapter. Does Vedantic doctrine strengthen ethical endeavour, or is it rather indifferent to it ? Is the final state which is aimed at by the sage one in which the ethical process is conserved and sublimated ? We have already touched upon this topic in connexion with our discussion of the ‘place of works’ in the Vedantic system, but we must now treat the question from a more general point of view. If Sankara is taken to be the typical Vedantist, the answer will largely tend to be that the ethical process is cut across and the ethical level is transcended. That which the pious man reaches by his moral striving is not final, and his ethical gains are not carried forward into the ultimate state, but rather put aside as T at the most an inadequate approach to what can best be attained by other methods. The Vedantists would for the most part agree with Bosanquet’s idea that perfection is a higher con¬ cept than the concept of the good, which latter belongs definitely to the stage of finite experience and not to reality as a whole. 1 With the Vedantist the attitude is closely allied to the implica¬ tions of a strict interpretation of the doctrine of maya, and to the contention that the Ultimate Reality is without qualities. In closer reference to ethics the essence of the Vedantic doctrine seems to be that, however earnest the ethical aspirant may be, and however widely he may extend his activities so that, in crucifixion of all selfishness, they may be devoted to the interests of others, it is impossible to get rid of egoity in the sphere of ethical endeavour; and yet without deliverance from egoity the final state cannot be attained. Full knowledge does not prevent selfishness and other kinds of evil by directing our desires to¬ wards a wider righteousness, but rather by destroying desire altogether. And, in general, ethics deals with ‘approach’, where¬ as the enlightened man is concerned with ‘recovery’. Ethics belongs essentially to the sphere of duality, and is not in place in any sphere in which activity is denied or transcended. Sankara, as we have seen, was not so doubtful as St. Paul 1 Of. Roger, Recent American and English Philosophy, 278. PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA m about the possibility of fulfilling the works of the law, but he held that, even if the law were fulfilled, it was powerless to effect the emancipation of the soul. He thought that ethical endeavour even of the highest kind was impossible except in conjunction with the assertion of individuality and personality; and that, because the ego cannot be got rid of in moral progress, and yet the assertion of the ego renders impossible the attainment of the highest state, the sphere of ethics must be left behind. Morality must be transcended if the end of ethics, viz. perfec¬ tion, is to be attained. He hardly seems to entertain the idea of a gradual transformation from the incomplete to the complete, from the imperfect to the perfect. As Deussen puts At, ‘Moral transformation remained foreign to Indian thought.^ A con¬ tradiction lies at the very heart of ethics. In order that ethics may reach its goal, the annihilation of the self, ethics itself must disappear. The argument is that while we remain ourselves, it will be impossible for us to resolve this contradiction. We cannot comprehend how the sphere of the ego may be transcended. But it would almost seem as if the Vedanta, because we cannot understand, gave us permission to be dogmatic about the matter, and to argue that, the transformation of the will being an un¬ intelligible mystery, we are at liberty to pass altogether to another point of view at which the difficulty will disappear,!, e. we may abandon the sphere of ethics. It may be noticed that the attitude to a certain extent implies a confusion between selfishness and ‘selfness’, and a consequent equal condemnation of them. We have frequently had occasion to consider this view in connexion with the Vedanta philosophy, and it would seem to take for granted that ethical endeavour is and must always be deficient, unless not only selfishness but also selfness can be transcended. The mood is akin to that which Prof. Wenley ascribes to Schopenhauer, ‘To gain perfection man must divest himself of his own self-hood, and be received back again into the uncon¬ scious reality of will, where nothing is distinguishable.’ 1 . It is a direct consequence of what we have seen to be the prevailing Vedantic view of the relation of the individual soul to Brahman, and we would thus seem to be justified in linking with this latter » Wenley, Aspects of Pessimism, 263. 1 Deussen, 17. 174 PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA view our treatment of the ethical doctrine of the Vedanta. Depreciation of the individual seems to result inevitably in a depreciation of ethics. We have already seen 1 that according to Sankara, activity, whether intellectual or practical, does not belong to the essence of the soul, and is alien to the sphere in which the higher know¬ ledge moves. Works can give only transitory felicity and their results are not carried forward into the ultimate condition of the soul. They are ascetic rather than meritorious in that they do not produce the higher emancipating knowledge but simply prepare for it. Good works cannot improve the soul because, being unchangeable, it is incapable of degrees of perfection. Neither can works aiming at the establishment of valuable social conditions be thoroughly efficacious. They may loosen the bonds of selfishness by extending our interests so that they become coincident with those of our fellows and we become more perfect instruments of the common will. But we are instruments still, and therefore not free in our own soul, and we remain in bondage to the temporal, for even the most perfect community is affected by the transitory characteristics of the age to which it belongs. We must here, of course, repeat our warnings against one¬ sided judgements, and avoid the conclusion that, because San¬ kara assigns only subordinate importance to works, this is equivalent to saying that they have no importance at all. We must freely admit, as Prof. K. Shastri so well and so vigorously points out, 2 that there is a close connexion between Vedanta teaching and the practice of the higher virtues, and that, on the other hand, to press a phrase like ‘the enlightened man may live as he pleases’, so as to make it support a charge of antinomianism, is to do a grave injustice to the system as a whole. It may be noticed, however, in passing, that European writers are not the greatest sinners in respect of this charge. We find an Indian judgement of the most severe type, e. g. in R. C. Bose’s book on Hindu Philosophy. After describing the Pantheism of the Vedanta by the harsh name ‘pandiabolism’, he goes on to say: The sys¬ tem has proved a refuge of lies to many a hardened sinner. The perplexed minds which have found shelter in its solution of the i p . iao. * K. Shastri, Chapter IV, passim. PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA 175 problem of existence are few indeed, but the number of wicked hearts which have been composed to sleep by the opiate of its false hope, is incalculable. 5 But, surely, in opposition to Mr. Bose, we may be permitted to point out that ‘to live as one pleases 5 may mean, not to neglect morality, but to be indepen¬ dent of rule with the superiority of the artistic to the mechanical spirit and the freedom and joyousness of the former. There is much truth in Prof. Radhakrishnan's saying that 4 The pure and perfect are laws unto themselves 5 . 1 , But at the same time the question remains whether, when all is said and done, the Vedanta can assign that ultimate validity to ethics which would seem to be required if individual and social life is to reach and abide in perfection. Is it indeed necessary to hold that the highest ethical state and the highest condition of the soul must be different from each other ? Can we sympathize with Kirtikar when he asks, in reference to the world of ethical action, ‘Of what value is a toy elephant to one who understands that it is only a toy? 5 Or can we agree with the dualism which is implied in his further queries and answers, Ts philosophical truth to be sacrificed lest its recognition should disturb the ethical ideal? 5 , and again, ‘Truth ought not to be sacrificed to practical life 5 . 2 To many a very different point of view would appeal with greater force; they would hold that if such a contradiction were to arise, we should at least consider the possibility of modifying, not truth itself—which is impos¬ sible—but our particular conception of truth. As Rashdall puts it, ‘Our conception of the highest good may be inadequate, but we certainly shall not attain to greater adequacy or a nearer approach to ultimate truth by flatly contradicting our moral judgements. It would be just as reasonable to argue that, be¬ cause the law of gravitation might be proved, from the point of view of the highest knowledge, to be an inadequate statement of truth, . . . therefore we had better assume that, from the point of view of God, there is no difference between attraction and repulsion. 53 Our main problem here may be put in the form of an inquiry whether the ethical life can be maintained in its fullness on the 1 Radhakrishnan, I. 507. 3 Kirtikar, 106. 3 Rashdall, Philosophy and Religion, 68. i 7 6 PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA basis of that doctrine of abstract and unmodified identity be¬ tween ourselves and the characterless Absolute which would seem to be the resultant of Sankara’s interpretation of the Vedanta? Does not Ramanuja’s guidance seem preferable in this connexion if we are to preserve the health of our ethical life; if, when our precepts are pressed to their logical conclusions, these are not, in the case of the less worthy, to permit of moral deterioration or at least indifference, and, in the case of the more worthy, to bring about the morally reassuring, but theoretically disconcerting result that their practice will turn out to be con¬ siderably in advance of their principles. The more worthy seem in the sphere of practical life to live more earnestly than their principles encourage them to do, and as regards them there is much truth in Mr. Archer’s saying that ‘Hindu philo¬ sophy is after all too human to be logical’. 1 Undoubtedly, the strict Vedantist would show a tendency to answer in the negative this question as to whether ethics is compatible with a doctrine of abstract identity, but, on the ground that ethics does not belong to the highest level, the denial would be made without any serious compunction. Gn the other hand, this surrender of a valuable constituent of human life seems to us to be without sufficient justification. Weare inclined rather to inquire further into the reason for this dualism between the identity conception and the ethical point of view, in the hope that possibly the ideal may be stated in such a way as not to necessitate a depreciation of ethics, which depreciation, we repeat, seems to us to be an implicit criticism of any ideal which involves it. In citing objections on ethical grounds to this identity ideal we must be careful not to make use of the crude charge of blas¬ phemy, a method of attack which formerly was favoured by critics of the Vedantic position. It used to be argued that to equalize man with God was ‘to arrogate divinity for humanity ; and the suggestion was added that such an equation, when applied to the individual, meant that each man could claim that he was already godlike and therefore did not stand in need of ethical improvement. The enthusiastic language of some Vedantists, e.g. that of Swami Vivekananda in portions of his 1 India and the Future , 23. PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA 177 book on Jnanayoga, may have given colour to this criticism. But we think that it is alien to the true meaning of the Vedanta, and that the resulting attitude, though not perhaps the theoretical basis, is more truly given in Prof. Radhakrishnan’s language in reference to the Upanishads, ‘God is not in man in such obvious fashion that he can possess Him absentmindedly and without a struggle. God is present as sFpotentia or a possibility.. . . The God in man is a task as well as a fact, a problem as well as a possession. 51 Moreover, even as regards the theoretical aspect, it is but just to notice that the criticism seems to proceed from a slight misunderstanding of the point of view. The Vedantists were not thinking primarily of ethical completeness but of a fundamental identity above the ethical level. It seems unfair therefore to subject them to charges which can have relevance only on the ethical level. The true point at issue is why they are so unwilling to be judged from the ethical standpoint, and why they are so reluctant to permit our ethical aspirations to find completion in an answering metaphysical reality. We cannot at one and the same time accuse them of transcending the ethical level and condemn them for claiming complete fulfil¬ ment of their ethical aspirations. We cannot pass judgement against them in a court whose jurisdiction they deny, though we may quite legitimately ask whether they are justified in denying thejurisdiction, and whether their refusal is not seriously prejudicial to the moral law, which they would desire to have upheld except perhaps when they happen to be in an^ultra- philosophical mood 5 . Yet the charge of blasphemy would seem to have at the back of it, not the idea that the Vedantists avoid ethical judgement, but that they claim ethical attainment, and this latter accusation can certainly not be made in general terms. Finally, we must remember that a charge of blasphemy is always apt to provoke a reaction in the form of a counter-charge to the effect that those who argue on the other side wish to minimize the closeness of the connexion between man and God. This would also be unjust, for the objection of the opponents of identity is not to closeness of connexion but to the special interpretation of that connexion as being expressible only in terms of bare identity. Emphasis upon the identity conception 1 Radhakrishnan, I. 209. N x 7 8 PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA is peculiarly disastrous in respect of the claim of ethics to un¬ restricted jurisdiction and paramount importance in human life. Ethics essentially demands a certain amount of transcendence and objective reference both in the direction of other men and in the direction of God. As regards the first or human reference it is frequently argued that nothing could be more efficacious as a spring of social service than this feeling of identity between ourselves and other men. We can love our neighbour truly, it is said, only if we can realize our oneness with our neighbour, only if we can in thought obliterate all superficial and artificial distinctions. It is possible to obey the injunction to love one’s neighbour as oneself only if we can recognize our own self in that of our neighbour. Deussen stresses this argument very markedly, and a recent writer has applied it to modern social conditions : ‘It seems at times that we may be approaching a change whereby the universal self-consciousness 1 that inspires life to-day, may be exchanged for a consciousness that sees the whole as one; self-consciousness it is that has built up the form of competitive society which we see everywhere and have seen throughout history. A new reaction to life would produce in¬ evitably a new form of society.’ 1 But, in reply to this, it must be noticed that a mere feeling of identity taken by itself may work both ways. It may make us feel—and probably often does so— that we should help our neighbour because he is one with us; but logically it might quite as well enable us to argue that we are justified in promoting our own interests because, our neigh¬ bour being one with us, his interests are identical with ours, and therefore in promoting our interests we are ipso facto promoting his. It might even, if we were to follow Schopenhauer s applica¬ tion of this thought, be used as a support of injustice. Why should we grieve, he asks, over undeserved suffering falling upon another, for, those who suffer on the one hand, and those who, on the other hand, through wrongdoing either escape suffering or cause suffering, are one and the same, and therefore suffering in the last analysis really falls where it is due.- The difficulty would appear to arise from a defect in the con¬ cept of identity. It is not differentiating enough to provide a ■ The word is here used apparently in the narrow and popular sense. a Willcocks, Between the Old World and the New, 360. PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA 179 basis for social ethics. Absorption in another personality is a metaphor derived from physical analogies and is not fully appro¬ priate to the more heterogeneous and more organic relations of human beings. It is to be noticed that Vedantic teaching does not properly detach itself from the original physical significance of the metaphor, and constantly hovers between the idea of ab¬ sorption on the level of unconsciousness and absorption on the level of consciousness. Social action is dependent indeed on sympathy, but on an intelligent and imaginatively discriminating sympathy which differentiates the object of sympathy from our¬ selves. Mere identity based on abstraction and negation can¬ not take the place of sympathy for the different, especially when, over against this comparatively vague and weak bond of associa¬ tion, we have to take account also of the continuing influence of the karmic idea, with its implications of externality and individualism which serve to strengthen the popular assump¬ tion of non-transferable destinies. As Solovyof puts it, ‘The removal of barriers between the self and the not-self, or im¬ mediate identification, is merely a figure of speech and not an expression of real fact. Like the vibration of chords that sound in unison, the bond of compassion between human beings is not simply identity but harmony of the similar.’ 1 Further, an identification with others which is associated with a denial of their reality as individuals is absolutely fatal to ethical endeavour of a social character. If looking at human beings sub specie aeternitatis and through the mediation of the concept of strict identity leads us to regard them as small and insignificant, if not almost futile, as individuals, we cannot direct our efforts persistently towards their welfare. We can help men aright only if we can regard them as existences having rights in themselves, I ‘independent centres of action and sources of feeling’^whose 1 interests may not be absorbed in ours but with whom we may enter into the unity of common aims. Social service demands the reality of the social order and its members. As an Indian writer puts it,j £ To live and work for the essentially untrue is hardly an inspiring and convincing creed, and to think of others when there is none else to be thought of, is almost to make a mockery of intelligence.’ 3 J; 1 Solovyof, Justification of the Good, 68. a B. K. Shastri, 229. i8o PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA In reference to God also, ethics, if it is to be properly estab¬ lished, demands transcendence and objectivity. The essence of the ethical spirit is aspiration, and aspiration is possible only in connexion with the ‘other—the ‘other 5 which is also the higher. The conception of identity is useful in giving us confidence that we have within us the potentiality of the divine, and that there¬ fore ethical endeavour is not meaningless. But if this concep¬ tion is pressed too far or too exclusively, it is apt to result in a view which might render the ethical life superfluous. Prof. Radhakrishnan has foreseen this danger and has done his best to guard against it in the passage which we have quoted above. 1 But the danger is apt to recur with disconcerting frequency in connexion with the Vedanta. If we are already one with God, there is little point in striving ethically to become Godlike. When there is identity, sufficient room is not left for the stages of approach. When we have already arrived at a destination we do not concern ourselves very much with the toilsome and dusty road. It is an outgoing of desire and love which alone can inspire ethical action in times of crisis, and indeed on ordinary occasions also; and if the love is simply another form of the love wherewith a man loves himself, its uplifting force is diminished. An Indian writer protests in another connexion against the charge that the Vedanta rouses no enthusiasm for God, by pointing out that ‘it is obviously wrong to suppose that (the devotee) has no love for Brahma, unless one is prepared to say of him that he does not love himself 5 . 3 Now at first sight such a statement has a superficial resemblance to Spinoza's doctrine that our highest love to God is the love wherewith God loves himself. But the emphasis is different, and this difference of emphasis is all-important from the point of view of ethics. Our starting-point makes all the difference. If, when we are thinking of the identity of human and divine love, we think first of the love wherewith God loves himself, we may lose little in respect of inspiration as we carry the thought downwards to human life. But if, on the other hand, we begin by saying that our highest spring of action is a love similar to that wherewith we love ourselves, then our ethical endeavour would seem to be weakened at its very source; for to love oneself—in the case of 1 p.185. a Kirtikar, 121. PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA i8i the weak man at least—may demand very little effort. Ethics cannot exist except in association with a feeling of uplift, and it would seem to demand such an interpretation of aspiration to¬ wards God as is given by Solovyof: ‘However complete’, he says,‘the feeling of our inner unity with God may be, it never becomes a consciousness of mere identity, of simple meiging into one. The feeling of unity is inseparably connected with the consciousness that the Deity with which we are united, and which acts and reveals itself in us, is something distinct and in¬ dependent of us, that it is prior to us, higher and greater than we.’ 1 And in ethics there is further involved, as the essence of the process, the establishment of harmony between the im¬ perfect in us and the objective perfection in God. This leads to another thought. It may be argued that identity, even though it leaves no room for ‘approach’, yet does not rule out progress, inasmuch as it provides for recovery and return, for ‘a becoming of the soul what it has always been, a revival of its true nature’. 2 This would certainly relieve us greatly of our difficulty, were the recovery based upon identification with a God possessed of all perfect qualities. But when we have to do with a characterless Brahman, recovery of identity with Him means no thin g that has importance for ethics. It implies a re¬ lapse upon quietism, a virtual abandonment once more of the ethical point of view. Now we are quite willing to admit that this abandonment of the ethical struggle may frequently arise from a vivid apprehension of the grace of God, and from a pro¬ found and praiseworthy feeling of dissatisfaction with our own attainments, from the consciousness that what we actualize in our character can never be adequate to the ideal. But is abandon¬ ment the only possible outcome of this feeling ? Because we are dissatisfied, need we cease to struggle for satisfaction along the lines which our duty has hitherto prescribed for us? Because moral aspiration is insatiable, must the moral level be altogether transcended ? Must we sink our ideal in the characterless- un¬ known depths of our own being, vaguely recognized as identical with the Being of God? Should we not rather project our ideal on to the heights of the Divine Reality, justified thereto by what would seem to be the direct and obvious answer to the simple 1 Solovyof, op. cit., 164, 3 Muller, S. S. 168. 182 PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA . question as to whence came our ideal ? Surely our sense of the inadequacy of our objective moral achievement does not de¬ mand that we should become merely subjective and negative. Rather does it send our thoughts onward to the thought of a fuller objective realization, not in us but in God. But if this is so, then ethics refuses to be satisfied with a characterless Absolute. It demands a Reality having a character which may constitute our goal, however distant it may be from our present attainment. And so we are led to ask whether the difficulties in the way of finding a moral ideal in God are so insuperable as many Vedantists would make out. Such objec¬ tions may be first of all connected with the depreciation of activity in general. Action, according to the Vedantists, is ir¬ relevant in connexion with the highest knowledge, because ac¬ tion has to do with what has not yet come into existence, whereas knowledge has to do with that which eternally is, that which is not susceptible of increase or decrease, or of any kind of altera¬ tion. From this it follows, according to the argument we are considering, that the Eternal self cannot be improved by the addition of good qualities or the removal of defects. Therefore moral predicates are out of place in connexion with any ultimate and unchangeably real existence; for the conception of goodness is unmeaning except in connexion with activity, and unless a distinction of good from evil is allowed. The idea underlying the reluctance to make use of moral characterization would thus seem to be that goodness emerges from a sense of incomplete¬ ness and consequently from desire, and that when incomplete¬ ness and the longing to be rid of it are ruled out, then goodness has no place. But over and above our reluctance to accept the view that desire is inherently evil, and the suspicion, which we share with Mr. Archer, that the demand for the annihilation of desire is a kind of ‘hedging 5 against destiny, 1 we cannot agree with the further assumption that the goodness of a thing depends on our desiring it. It is not good because we desire it; it is rather desired because it is good, because it has inherent value, objec¬ tively and not merely subjectively, because it seems to have an inalienable right to a significant place in a scheme of reality 1 Of. India and the Future , 73. PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA 183 having a definite character. Our sense of value is an apprecia¬ tion of objective conditions; and desire implies a recognition of a standard of values not dependent on the desire itself. Thus, even if we were to grant the contention that desire ought to dis¬ appear, the value would remain as a recognition of the ultimate meaning of the world. If, on the other hand, we are indisposed to go the length of allowing that all desire is evil, our demand that there should be objective justification for our highest desires is correspondingly strengthened. Further, although we may be in the habit of applying the word ‘good’ to what shows signs of a satisfactory measure of approach towards an ideal, yet the word may also be applied simply as a description of the highest we know; and the inapplicability to the Absolute of the first sense need not preclude the application of the second. Not only may we apply ethical predicates to the ultimate, but it seems to us that we must do so, if our ethical struggle is not to be meaningless and futile. Ethics, as we have contended, demands a sphere of reality in which it may work, and a reason¬ able faith that the basis of this reality may be characterized in such a way as to give strength and encouragement for the struggle with certain disconcerting aspects of experience. Prof. Radhakrishnan illustrates the need in his criticism of Buddhism when he says that 'Buddhism establishes the enormous diffi¬ culty of having a pure morality independent of spiritual values’. 1 The problem of ethics is to deal with the evil and sorrow of the world, and these cannot be dealt with adequately simply by relegating them to a sphere of unreality. As Principal Galloway puts it, 'Spiritual selves claim to be real, and our consciousness of freedom and our sense of moral evil decline to be relegated to the category of illusion.’ 2 Evil cannot be overcome by deny¬ ing its reality, especially when this is accompanied by a denial of the reality of the good as well. Evil cannot be overcome by negation, but only by a positive reality. We cannot agree with Prof. Shastri that an unreal life can be worthy in the highest sense. 3 Selfishness, e.g., can be overcome not by merely think¬ ing about its disappearance but by an assertion or at least a con¬ sciousness of objective unselfishness. All great virtues are the 1 Radhakrishnan, I. 608. 3 Religion and Modern Thought, 216. 3 Cf. B, K, Shastri, p. xxi, i8 4 PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA results of faith in a positive impact of goodness; and, ultimately, we arrive at the necessity of a belief that the quality of goodness can be used to describe the deepest reality of the universe, and that we are not without justification for the assurance that help for the combating of evil may come to us from the innermost shrine of the Being of God. To be told that, on the emergence of true knowledge, evil will necessarily be thought out of existence is hardly sufficient to comfort us whilst we are still struggling under untoward condi- tions of everyday life; and in the face of actual sorrow, especially that which comes to us from the suffering of others, whom we love, to tell us that this suffering is an illusion is not far re¬ moved from pitilessness. We cannot, e.g., place ourselves very readily at the point of view of Prof. Das Gupta, when he says, The sorrow around us has no fear for us, if we remember that we are naturally sorrowless and blessed in ourselves. The pes¬ simistic mood loses all terrors, as it closes in absolute optimistic confidence in one’s own self and the ultimate destiny and goal of emancipation.’ 1 The emphasis here is still laid upon deliverance and negative freedom, upon the cultivation of a mood of philosophical de¬ tachment. And when, in the inevitable clash between such a mood and the ordinary experience of life, our thought swings over to the opposite extreme, we are not much helped, as regards ethical support, by the doctrine of karma in the form in which it appears in the Vedanta. This doctrine was intended by Sankara to save us from uncomfortable questioning about the justice of God. But we establish our theodicy—if, indeed, we do establish it—at a very great price. Even if we slur over our difficulties about the beginning of things, and accept the ex¬ planation that there is no beginning, we find that we are the resultants of previous conditions which have been unfolding themselves for untold ages. We are bereft of the privilege of responsibility even for the evil that we do. We find that all causality, after all, really belongs to God; or that we are in the grasp of an inexorable destiny v^ithin whose processes there is only cyclic change, and with regard to which there is no hope of progress except in the negative sense that we may attain ever 1 Das Gupta, I. 77. PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA 185 more completely to the true knowledge which will give us, not victory, but escape. Nothing seems to be provided between the extremes we have indicated. It is a case of either bondage or abstract freedom. We can escape only by thinking of our im¬ prisonment as a dream, and not by breaking down the walls of the prison-house. We do not sublimate or consecrate the condi¬ tions of the actual, but stand apart from the perplexing prob¬ lems of ordinary life, apart in theory at least, if—fortunately— not always in practice. And does the freedom which we are promised satisfy the aspiring soul ? Is it the freedom that we desire, or—to go one step farther back—can we rest in this theoretical knowledge that there is a freedom without our prison-house ? Rather is it the freedom of the desert, of the wide empty spaces or the boundless sea: So lonely ’twas that God himself Seemed scarcely there to be. 1 And it is just possible that by its very vacuity such freedom may become a new kind of bondage. Activity which can find no outlet produces subjectively the same kind of feeling as restraint. A character in a recent novel seems to express such a mood, * “Ah”, she mocked, “wait till you’re so free that you just daren’t do what you like. Wait till you’re so free that you can be here one minute and there another. Wait till you are so free that you can see the four walls of your freedom and the iron-bound door that will let you out into the open air of slavery, if only there were some one to open it .” y% A similar mood is set forth by another writer who speaks of the great hours of experience when The soul of man has . . . suddenly hated its so-called freedom and returned to some bondage dearer than freedom’, and of the transition ‘from a condition of “liberty” to some blessed state of bondage’; adding the reflection, ‘perhaps the truth is that we are made for bondage, but it must be bondage to something which moves or to someone who loves’. 3 These quotations suggest that there is a higher freedom than merely abstract and negative freedom—a freedom which is hinted at in the well- known words, ‘whose service is perfect freedom’, a freedom 1 Ancient Manner. s Michael Arlen, The Green Hat, 131, „ 3 P r * J* A. Hutton, Guidance from Francis Thompson in Matters of Faith, 49. 186 PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA which is allied with interest in the actual, with a discernment of the problems of the actual, and an attempt to solve these through the inspiration of a faith that the ultimate purpose of the actual and its essential meaning is the establishment of the good. In other words we desire a freedom which will not merely tell us that there is liberty outside the prison-house of our lower desires and mundane existence, but which will enable us to break down its walls and pass out, having victorious strength of character in ourselves, and so desirous of the salva¬ tion of our fellows that the prison walls may not so easily close again either upon them or upon us. Asceticism and negation generally are meaningless, except as J they are steps on the way to moral affirmation. We must pass from negative to positive freedom. The former, when rein¬ forced by indifference, may give way before the downward persistence of our lower desires; the latter lays hold on the prin¬ ciple of life, and cherishes the faith that all moral endeavour will be taken up into and transformed by the deepest Power and Order of the world—there shall not be one lost good. We must not, of course, lose sight of the value that underlies the negative attitude to morality. It is right that we should not, through over-scrupulous attention to the means, lose sight of the end of our moral endeavour; and negation may simply be an exaggera¬ tion of the warning against legalism. But it is equally necessary that we should not transform a subject attitude of caution into a metaphysical conclusion, and deny to morality any place in the ultimate end; we should not so conceive the end as to de¬ prive the means of all importance. It is for us rather to Learn, by a mortal yearning, to ascend— Seeking a higher object. 1 If our aim is simply to get out of the samsara, then we shall not be encouraged to faithful observance of the stages of the pro¬ cess. A doctrine of metaphysical emptiness may not be very far removed from moral indifference, unless we are willing to look upon morality not merely as a disciplinary struggle, but as a positive achievement. After all, end and means are correlative conceptions, and the end can have significance only if the means 1 Wordsworth, Laodamia. PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA 187 also are taken as real. As has been said, ‘It is the peril of the Mystic that he is inclined to forget the Way in the end. The peril of the man of Reason is that he cannot see the end for the dust he raises by the way.’ 1 We may add that it is the duty of the moral philosopher to avoid the extremes of both the Mystic and the man of Reason. We have been urging that, if morality is to have a proper basis, it requires objectification or a reaching outwards to a Divine Reality of positive moral character; but we must em¬ phasize also the necessity of a feeling of reality in regard to our subjective point of initiation. Ethics cannot be secure if as¬ sociated with a depreciation of personality. And we demand not only a feeling of reality but a feeling of value. It should be impossible to describe the individual soul in the words even of Ramanuja—usually inclined towards a more positive attitude—• as f a mere wretched glow-worm\ z In drawing attention to the need of personal persistence we must not be thought to be laying ourselves open to the charge of selfishness or concern with material reward either in this world or the next. Despite any possible misunderstandings, we cannot relinquish the idea that the completion of personal efficiency is an essential element in the moral ideal, or the demand that we shall be allowed to find ourselves again in an eternal Reality receptive of the good. Personality must be regarded, not as an accident or anomaly, but as normal to the universe. In fact we may relate the argu¬ ment to the present tense rather than to the future, and we may 'point out that our present appreciation of reality is essentially bound up with the exercise of our personality, and that we cannot sacrifice this without reducing our life, as well as our hopes, to the vagueness and instability of a dream. So from the present we may pass to the future as to an extension of the same consciousness, and, considering both present and future together, may quite naturally point out that if the life of the individual is not to be continued in the future, a feeling of impuissancede vivre will descend upon him, and he will be inclined to take up an attitude of indifference even in regard to the present. We are not urging that, with the loss of the hope of personal im- 1 Joergens, art. in Time and Tide } Sept. 1924. 2 S. B. E, XLVIII. 469. 188 PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA mortality, the fear of hell will be lessened and the expectation of reward will disappear. Our argument has a deeper basis; we are thinking rather of contribution than of claim, and all that we ask is the continuance of the opportunity to make that con¬ tribution. If, as we think is the case, our contribution cannot be separated from ourselves and consists rather in what we are than in what we give, all that we ask is that this gift of our personality itself may be assigned a place of permanent value in the ultimate constitution of things. We believe that the perfec¬ tion of the whole cannot be secured without the perfection, permanence, and utmost expansion of the parts—which parts we are. And if the high philosopher still shakes his head in unbelief, and speaks, wistfully, if not contemptuously, of pious wishes divorced from facts, we may quote in support of our contention for the reality of the individual the common-sense appeal of Sir Oliver Lodge : 4 If any philosopher tells you that you do not exist, . . . that you are an automaton without free¬ will, that all your actions are determined by outside causes—■ then appeal must be made to twelve average men, unsophis¬ ticated by special studies. This is not an appeal to the mob as against the philosopher, but an appeal to the experience of un¬ told ages against the studies of a generation.^ s In our discussion of the place of works in the Vedantic system we have already spoken of the difficulty, within that system, of arriving at any practical conception of the Kingdom of God. Wofks of social service are regarded certainly as one of the best means of purifying the soul, but as little more. In fact the further idea is hinted at that, if the permanence of the results of unselfish labours is dwelt upon, the individual will become the prisoner of the good he has wrought and thus fail to win deliverance. It were better therefore, it is urged, that this world should be regarded simply as a place of sanctification and atonement, and that no thought of the establishment of a king¬ dom of righteousness should obsess the soul. It were better that the enlightened man should remember that 'all relations lose their significance in the one eternal life'. 3 In such a position once more the foundations of ethics would seem to be weakened. At our highest, we strive for the estab- 1 Quoted in the ffibbert Journal, July 1926. 2 Kirtikaiyi22. PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA 189 lishment not only of personal but of social values, and, unless we can feel that there is a promise of the permanence of the results of such efforts, in the upbuilding of a community of free and noble spirits, the efforts themselves are apt to slacken. We desire that from our ultimate ideal we may derive an incentive for the service of the community; and we feel that, if the way is blocked in this direction, our moral life in its highest exercise will become futile, and bereft also of the inspirational value of association with the good in other lives. From the conception of the true Self which is so strongly emphasized in the Vedanta, such a way of expansion ought to open out. As Happel puts it, 'The true Ego is present only in elementary form in separate human individuals. It is only in organic communion with others that it wins its higher potentiality, and it attains its complete fullness only in the personality of God, in communion with whom separate personalities can reach their truest development and independence, so that God then truly is all in all.' 1 But our final question is whether in the Vedanta such a way of emergence and expansion has been left open ? We are doubt¬ ful if this question can be answered in the affirmative. In application to the Vedanta there is much truth in the words of Gaird, 'To remain at the negative point of view is as disastrous as never to have reached it. For to deny the place of passion and desire is to cut oneself off from all concrete human interests; to shut the spirit up in the cell of its own self-contained inde¬ pendence instead of finding a home for it in the wide world of human good/ 3 Eucken also complains in special reference to the Vedanta of the cleavage which it introduces between The height of the inner life and the rest of existence’, and complains that by its method 'man attains a purely inward life and that there is no path leading from this inwardness to the wide field of life’. 3 For a judgement of much the same character as Eucken’s, but in our opinion excessively severe, we may compare Archer’s India and the Future, 73. 'There is something no doubt in the rule of practical philosophy which bids us not found the livability of life upon external satisfac- '■ 1 Happel, 175. ■ 3 Life of Caird, 314. 3 Cf. also the present writer’s Pantheism and the Value of Life, 331 ff. 190 PLACE OF ETHICS IN THE VEDANTA tions but rather upon internal resources of which nothing can deprive us. Up to a certain point this is true wisdom; carried beyond that point it lands us in sheer inanities of egoism which strike at the root of all human association. This is so evident that Indian thinkers have expended a great deal of ingenuity in the attempt to reconcile a philosophy which denies all value to life with an ethical system based, as all ethical systems must be, on the assumption that life is supremely valuable and the test of all other values. . . . The doctrine of detachment, passionlessness, indifference, as a cure for the in¬ herent evil of existence, is not a profound one at all, but is merely the exaggeration of a common and somewhat pusillanimous mode of procedure. In its exaggerated form it is violently anti-social and consequently incompatible with any rational system of ethics. The demand for modification and reconstruction which we have made from the point of view of ethics really leads us on to the religious demand that God should be brought, not into negative, but into positive organic relation with the world; that He should enter into contact with history and the present en¬ deavours of men, that He should take into and upon Himself the burden of the suffering and evil of the world and of our misuse of human freedom, that He should redeem us from our unfitness and our evil, and welcome us to fullness of communion and ser¬ vice and to a permanent place of value in His kingdom. A love of the world and of the human beings in it, a trust in it and in them planted at the very heart of God, and a readiness to give His very self for the redemption of the world, or in the language of the New Testament ‘to give His only begotten Son’, can alone satisfy the hearts of men. We shall consider the religious value of the Vedanta in our concluding chapter, but before we go on to this most important topic of all, we may set our whole discussion in clearer light by devoting a chapter to a comparison of Vedantic teaching with certain conceptions of modern philosophy. VIII SOME COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT E VEN the briefest study of speculation in other parts of the world will have the result of deepening the impression of the unity of human thought. It is possible to find parallels to Vedantic teaching in many Western systems, and illustrations of cases in which like elements in fundamental assumptions are followed by conclusions also similar serve to make more obvious the essential and wholly natural implications of such elements. In this section we shall take ‘modern* in the wide sense usually accepted in histories of philosophy, and for the most part, though not entirely, we shall confine our attention to those philosophies which present broad similarities to the Vedanta, especially in respect of intellectualistic tendency. A study of the Vedanta inevitably invites comparison first of all with Spinoza amongst ‘modern* philosophers. Even in the diverse judgements which have been passed upon him there are suggestive parallels, for, just as in the Vedanta, it seems difficult to assess the comparative importance of the mystical and in¬ tellectual elements. On the one hand he has been called ‘a God- intoxicated man*.: When Renan unveiled the Spinoza monu¬ ment in The Hague, he pointed reverently to the windows of the house where Spinoza died, and said,.‘Maybe it was from there that God was seen nearest,’ and a recent critic, who was, in general, not given to emotion, had to confess that ‘one cannot read Spinoza in cold blood*. 1 On the other hand he has been described as an atheist and as ‘caring little for the world pro¬ vided it were only one*. In 1678, one year after his death, his Opera Posthuma was anathematized as ‘a godless book the like of which did not exist from the beginning of the world till now*, f and there have been echoes of this judgement ever since. The 7 starting-point of Spinoza’s philosophy is to be found in that aversion from the ordinary point of view, that discontent with the merely given, which we have found to be characteristic of the Vedanta, and his goal also reveals that close unity between 1 Iverach, Descartes and Spinoza, 132. igz COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA philosophical and religious interest which we have found to be characteristic of the earlier school of thought. It might be said with some amount of truth that Spinoza combines in himself the tendencies manifested both in Sankara and Ramanuja. He shows affinity with the former, in that he also regards God as the characterless infinite, in relation to which all determination is negation; and he connects himself with the latter in conceiving of God as the abode of all auspicious qualities, as that which ‘has absolutely infinite attributes of which each expresses infinite essence in its own kindVj Spinoza wavers between a negation of the world which is reminiscent for us of Sankara’s strict monism, and an accommodation to ordinary experience which recalls Ramanuja’s rehabilitation of the actual world. The relation between the individual and God is stated by him at times in terms of the identity relation of Sankara, and at other times he attributes to the individual an internal self-activity which is compatible only with Ramanuja’s ideal of communion as the final phase of religious attainment. It must be confessed, however, that the self-activity has no real place in his system, and his want of adequate provision for this reminds us of Ramanuja’s difficulties in adjusting divine and human causality, and in connexion with Spinoza himself it pro¬ voked the reaction towards individualism which followed imme¬ diately in the philosophy of Leibniz. But on the whole the closer affinity is with Sankara rather than with Ramanuja, at least if we confine ourselves to the logically consistent parts of Spinoza’s system. Although there is not in Spinoza the same abrupt separation between the higher and the lower orders of knowledge as in the Indian thinker, yet the higher, for the most part, turns out to be the negation of the lower rather than a development out of it. In both philosophers there is a strict adherence to the intellectual point of view and an almost exclu¬ sive reliance upon the activity of the mind as a means of obtain¬ ing deliverance. The means of escape for Spinoza are^adequate ideas’^ and, when in the individual life disturbance and misery are caused by our passions, it is by the power of the understand¬ ing that we may escape from their sway.\‘There is no modifica¬ tion of the body whereof we cannot form some clear and distinct 1 Ethics, I. 16. AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT 193 conception,’ and, ‘An emotion, which is a passion, ceases to be a passion, as soon as we form a clear and distinct idea thereof. 1 Here we have a close parallel to Sankara’s principle that the feeling of pain is due merely to the error of false imagination . At the same time we may notice in passing a slight difference in the operation of the enlightened understanding in the two philosophers. Spinoza is more inclined to dwell upon the application of knowledge to particular cases of the incidence of passion, and would attribute efficacy to the systematizing of the causes of passion according to ordinary scientific procedure; whereas Sankara is much more uncompromisingly negative, and is occupied with the general or total effect of emancipating knowledge in delivering us from the sum of conditions under which passions can be detrimentally operative. But although there may be a difference in degree of intensity of application, the acosmistic tendency is strong in both philo¬ sophers. By obedience to the higher knowledge we are to turn away our attention from the things of the world and withdraw into the depths of the soul. And just as in the Vedanta the root idea is the identification of Atman and Brahman, so with. Spinoza also it is by the deeper knowledge of the self within that we reach unity with the universal Self or God. This intense aspiration after unity leads Spinoza to a negative attitude to¬ wards the world and to a more or less abstract conception of God. Spinoza certainly bids farewell to the world with greater reluctance than Sankara, and his unity is always more open in the direction of diversity. His highest knowledge has been described as ‘thoughtfulness matured to inspiration’, and the idea of maturity very properly suggests the idea of gradual growth. But still, though the departure may be lingering and ultimately so formal as to permit of surreptitious return, the farewell is an important gesture. We are made to feel that extension as admitting of divisibility is a defective category, and that duration as permitting degrees is inapplicable to God. Our ordinary conceptions and classifications which aid us in our apprehension of the particular modes of being belong after ' all to the realm of illusion; it is in unity alone that we can find satisfaction. On the intellectual side there is perhaps a parallel 1 Ethics, V. 3 and 4. 3 S. B. E. XXXVIII. .64# O 194 COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA between Sankara’s conception of Ultimate Being as self-lumi¬ nous, arid Spinoza’s idea that Substance cannot be knowable except as self-luminous, because, if it were otherwise luminous, it would have qualities implying its dependence on other things. So negative and abstract is Spinoza’s thought that he really provides no proper passage from the undifferenced unity of Substance to the variety of the attributes. In striving to effect such a transition Spinoza finds himself in difficulties which have, in turn, involved his interpreters in seemingly interminable con¬ troversies as to the relation of attributes to substance within his system, exactly the difficulties over again of the Vedantic transition from the non-qualitative to the qualitative Brahman. Do the attributes constitute the essence of Spinoza’s substance or are they only fictions of the human intellect? If the former, what becomes of the doctrine of the undifferenced unity of Brahman; if the latter, whence came the minds capable of con¬ structing the fictions ? If all ordinary experience belongs to the region of names and forms—-to borrow a Vedantic phrase—will not thd imaging intellect also be a mere reflection, and partake of the ^general illusoriness, and whence can come the energy necessary for framing the illusion and becoming dissatisfied with it, as well as that general capacity for persistence which is so fundamental an element in Spinoza’s philosophy? If it is suggested in reply that these difficulties are themselves illusory, and will disappear with the disappearance of the illusion, we are simply compelled to press the question farther back and ask whence came the illusory point of view at all, for even an illusion must have a cause. In attempting to deal with this latter question—implicitly or explicitly put—Spinoza finds himself in much the same difficulty as Sankara in relation to the doctrine of maya. If the Absolute has first of all been defined as undifferentiated and changeless, it is impossible to get any creative energy out of it. And yet our ordinary experience—just because it is our experience—demands some explanation—demands the establishment of some rela¬ tion between that experience and the ultimate reality. This demand can be speciously satisfied only by a conception which, like the Vedantic maya, hovers between being and non-being; or, like the infinite modes of Spinoza, bridges only very ineffec- AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT 195 tively the gulf between static unity and dynamic multiplicity. Both are illogical attempts to prevent the finite world becoming, as Prof.Rogers puts it,‘a mere impertinence in the system , but into the further details of this parallel, theoretically illegitimate but practically most useful, it is not necessary to enter. We are more concerned with the effect of Spinoza’s views upon the importance of the individual both now and in any life _or lives—to come, and here we get another illustration of the fundamental deficiency of any purely intellectual system. Spinoza leaves no true place for the individual. As Caird says, ‘The idea of God on which Spinoza’s whole system is ostensibly based, is one which involves the denial of any reality or inde¬ pendence to the finite.’* And Spinoza obtains deliverance from the distressing aspects of the world—from its pain and its sorrow and its evil—partly by indifference and partly by acqui¬ escence. In actual life he was detached from ordinary human concerns; he lived through one of the most exciting periods of European history, and yet practically no reference to public affairs is to be found in his works. As Prof. Santayana puts it. ‘Lodged in his corner of the great house of nature he felt him¬ self humble, pensioned and at peace. He was proud of that great house and its glories; he venerated its economy, and never dreamt of reforming it .’3 This outward indifference was but the reflection of the internal attitude which seeks the solution of problems in thought alone and ends in escape rather than victory. For him distinction between good and evil was but a conditional and purely human contrivance, and was trans¬ cended in the Absolute. But although Spinoza had a stronger sense of the importance of society and a more modern and more sublime conception of the significance of natural law as revealed by science and interpreted by art, and, in consequence, never surrendered himself to the Vedantic extreme of indifference, yet when the p endulum of his thought swings over to an acknow¬ ledgement of the reality of the cosmos, he was apt, in his reac¬ tion from indifference, to fall a victim to a conception of inexor¬ able necessity and a denial of any true freedom to man. There is a parallel here to Sankara’s transition from negation to a 1 History of Philosophy, 305. # Caird, Spinoza, 298. 3 Introduction to Spinoza’s Ethics, p. ix. i 9 6 COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA modified acknowledgement of the law of karma. But neither in the negation of evil nor in the admission of its necessity, nor in freedom so restricted as almost to pass over into its opposite, can there be any abiding satisfaction for the soul of man. The freedom which he allows is that of complete identifica¬ tion with the Divine thought, and he expresses the unity through the help of the conception of the‘intellectual love of God’. The choice of the term might seem to arise from a sense of human worth and an inescapable consciousness of the reality of human endeavour, and it suggests the possibility of establishing a real and enduring relation between the individual and God. But Spinoza does not bring out the full significance of the term. Our love to God turns out to be the love wherewith God loves himself. In a very real sense Spinoza believes that a man becomes that of which he thinks. To think high thoughts is indeed the important influence in moral elevation. But when the process reaches the highest level, we find that (according to him) to think high thoughts is to become identified with our thought. The relation of identity is predominant and all differentiation disappears. In this way we get, no doubt, assur¬ ance of immortality, for ‘the spirit shares the fate of the object with which it identified itself, . . . and in caring for the eternal, it has ceased to care for that part of itself which can die’. 1 But our permanence is simply the permanence in God of our true thought, and does not carry with it the permanence of the thinker who formed the thought. Prof. Pringle-Pattison speaks truly of Spinoza’s 1 ‘substitution of the eternal life of thought . , . for immortality in the usual sense of a continued personal existenceV and it is this depreciation of continued personal existence which seems to be significant of the total effect of Spinoza’s system. | It might be interesting by way of contrast to follow out some of the consequences in the immediately succeeding Leibnizian philosophy of a revolt against this depreciation of the individual, and to find in the transition from Spinoza to Leibniz a parallel to some of the more striking differences between Sankara and Ramanuja. Leibniz, like Ramanuja, was disturbed by the fact that in the philosophy which preceded him the whole had seemed 1 Santayana, op. cit. xviii. s Idea of Immortality, 150. AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT 197 to swallow up the parts. Leibniz wished to hold fast to the principle of continuity, which might be said to be the result on the scientific level of a monism showing signs of a modification of its strictness. He also allowed, with Spinoza, the inadequacy of many of our. ordinary categories, holding, e.g., that the form of space, because of the infinite divisibility of any extended substance, would not enable us to reach any distinct reality of the individual. But at the same time, he was unwilling to abandon the reality of the individual, and conserved it in his doctrine of monads, which emphasized the idea that the reality of substance was intensive rather than extensive. He thus showed a tendency in the same direction as Ramanuja, although he went very much farther than the latter in his search for a satisfactory basis of individuality. It is curious also to notice that the difficulties which we have found to emerge in the Vedanta regarding the proper distribu¬ tion of responsibility for the suffering and evil of the world between God and man reappear in Leibniz. Wb found that Sankara in treating this problem had to take refuge in what was little more than a bare contradiction—‘The Lord indeed causes it (the individual soul) to act, but it acts itself.’ 1 Similarly, Leibniz, while showing that the soul is not determined to act from outside, yet, inasmuch as he holds that the individual is determined by the law of its own nature and that for that nature it is entirely dependent on God, escapes no more than Sankara from the necessity of refunding all causality ultimately into God. Before leaving Leibniz we may call attention to an interesting contrast between him.and the Vedanta in respect of the former’s law of the three stages of development. In the Vedanta we found that there were three stages of the soul’s progress—from ordinary waking consciousness, through dreaming sleep, to dreamless sleep J in Leibniz there are also three stages through which the monads may ascend from the lowest to the highest kind of perception. But the order is exactly reversed. The lowest are those which exist in a state of slumber or swoon, the middle class have attained to the phase of confused dreaming, whereas the highest of all have arrived at clear waking conscious¬ ness. The point is of small importance in itself, but it may 1 S. B. E. NXXVIII. 60. 198- COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA illustrate the great difference in total mental attitude between the Leibnizian philosophy and the Vedanta. From this digression we may turn back to systems presenting more of similarity with than of contrast to the Vedanta. We have in the course of our discussion already touched at con¬ siderable length on possible comparisons between the Vedanta and Kant, and we may devote a few paragraphs to the considera¬ tion of the philosophy of Fichte, which will, we think, afford further illustrations of the diminishing importance of the indi¬ vidual in any system of mystical or intellectualistic speculation, having identity as a fundamental concept. Prof. Rudolf Otto, in one of his recent addresses, speaks of the likeness between Sankara and Fichte as being so striking that one might almost speak of the rebirth of Indian philosophi¬ cal speculation in a German personality. 1 There is of course no direct relationship, but the gaze of both thinkers is turned in the same direction. With both, the pure Being, which is pure thought, is an absolute unity without variety, and relationship with it is attained by a higher kind of knowledge or intuition which is to be very carefully distinguished from the ordinary operations of the understanding. The ultimate Being is un¬ changeable and without creative energy, and in order to pass from it to the ordinary world we must posit a power which Fichte describes in terms almost identical with those which Sankara applies to may a. This appears to Prof. Otto to be the most surprising parallel of all, and it is indeed so striking that Fichte’s actual words may be quoted^ 4 There is only the One, unchangeable and eternal, and there is nothing beyond Him.^ All changeable and alterable is therefore most certainly nothing. ^ And its appearance is most certainly empty illusion. That I know. 1 On the other hand, Fichte is less inclined than Sankara to favour the idea of a world-illusion, and emphasizes rather the idea that the responsibility for the illusion rests upon the con¬ ceptual and discursive understanding of the individual thinker. Also, Fichte, notwithstanding his acceptance of the principle of unchangeableness, does not keep so consistently to this as does Sankara. He is inclined to modify it to a far greater extent and 1 Of. Mitteilungen der Deutschen Akademie f T)&c* 1925. AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT 199 opposes resolutely the idea of a God who is lifeless and static. Although our salvation is still according to Fichte based upon the relationship of identity between us and the divine, this rela¬ tionship will express itself in a life of action, even under the conditions of our present existence. The door of admission to the active service of humanity is opened wider with Fichte than with Sankara, because he conceives of God as active. But on the other hand, because the ideal relationship is for him still one of identity, the door is not opened quite far enough, and, because of ultimate metaphysical negation leading to a deprecia¬ tion of the individual, the desire for entrance is greatly weakened. As Schelling puts it in his interpretation of Fichte: ‘The goal of the finite Ego is enlargement of its sphere till the attainment of identity with the infinite Ego. But the infinite Ego knows no object, and possesses, therefore, no consciousness or unity of consciousness, such as we mean by personality. Consequently, the ultimate goal of all endeavour may also be represented as enlargement of the personality to infinity—that is to say, as its annihilation. The ultimate goal of the finite Ego—and not only of it but also of the Non-Ego,—the final goal, therefore, of the world—is its annihilation as a world .’ 1 1 This quotation brings together in significant conjunction abstraction as regards the ultimate principle and negation as regards the world and the individual. Before tur nin g to the broader and more intellectual develop¬ ment associated with Hegel and his followers, we may, in slight alteration of chronological order, make a passing reference to Schopenhauer. He is specially interesting for our purposes because of the vehemence with which he avows his indebted¬ ness to Indian philosophy, not so much for explicit statements of detailed conclusions as for the expression of a general spirit and of fundamental principles. He considers that his own principles are almost exactly similar to those of the earlier thinkers, and would independently lead to the same results. We find both in him and in them the same detachment from the or dinar y interests of life, the same yearning after deliverance, 1 Schelling, VomlchalsPrindp der Philosophie, quoted in Seth’s Hegelian- ism and Personality, 59. 200 COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA the same abstractness of procedure ? the same inclination to¬ wards an annihilating identification with a characterless infinite Reality. It is interesting also to notice the close connexion which Schopenhauer suggests between himself and Spinoza. He prides himself on having been born exactly one hundred and eleven years and one day after Spinoza, and evidently considers that the mantle of the earlier philosopher had fallen upon his shoulders. Schopenhauer finds it easy to reach the point of view at which the world appears to be an unreality. He tells us that v ‘he to whom man and all things have not appeared as phantoms, has no capacity for philosophy’. 1 Consequently, he disregards altogether the temporal developments of history, crushing the centuries together as he would the sections of a telescope, on the principle that we can learn nothing from the things of time except the necessity of going beyond them; and no doubt remembering also his conviction or experience that the transi¬ tion from common knowledge to enlightenment cannot be a gradual attainment but takes place suddenly. The ultimate reality is will; not consciousness, as in the Vedanta, but this will, equally with the Vedantic ultimate, is characterless, and the ideal relationship with it is absorption. In regard to this absorption there may indeed be several degrees of completeness, but the goal is that we should sink into a sheer sense of identity with the Ultimate. Even in stages before the final The true world in idea arises only when subject and object reciprocally fill and penetrate each other completely’. 2 Further, ‘whoever becomes so absorbed and lost in the perception of nature that he only continues to exist as the pure knowing subject, becomes in this way directly conscious that, as such, he is the condition, that is, the support of the world and all objective existence, for this now shows itself as dependent on his existence ’.3 This identification (set forth almost in Fichtean language) with the underlying restless striving will can provide no support for a sense of the value of the individual. His consciousness of individuality is a mere illusion, and immortality can consist only in the destruction of this illusion. Meanwhile an anticipation of essential identity may, as we have seen, make one patient in 1 Schopenhauer, 497. Mb. 235. 3 lb. 234. AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT 201 suffering injustice and unperturbed in inflicting it, just in so far as the doer or the sufferer is influenced by the consideration that those who inflict injury and those who suffer it are one and the same. Yet identity with this cosmic will cannot give final peace and rest according to Schopenhauer, for even the cosmic will is not absolute. Beyond the striving of the will he seems to descry a state of being in which it returns upon itself and ceases to be. Nothingness, at the dark impression of which he tells us we must not be alarmed, seeing that it is that ‘which we discern behind all virtue and holiness as their final goal’, would seem to be the consummation of our striving and our final verdict upon the world. In approaching the Hegelian philosophy it is tempting to rush at once to comparisons and allow the Hegelian opposition between Being and non-Being to remind us of the Vedantic Sat and Asat. But the parallel would hardly be exact, seeing that the Being of the Vedanta (whether unqualified or qualified) is the ultimate reality, whereas with Hegel Being is merely the simplest and least adequate interpretation of reality. Further, the relation between the two terms is on the whole more exclu¬ sive and finally oppositional in the Vedanta than in Hegel. We might be on surer ground, indeed, if we were to compare maya with the Hegelian principle of negation from which Hegel shows a tendency to derive a principle of actualization. Kirtikar, e.g., describes maya and avidya as ‘neither more nor less than this negative aspect of Being explaining the Becoming’. 1 It will perhaps be most useful to place Hegel in relation to the Vedanta through the mediation of a consideration of Schelling’s position. The latter, after the manner of the stricter Vedanta, practically sacrifices difference to unity. He is inclined towards an Absolute which is like ‘the night in which all cows are black’ —to use Hegel’s phrase. It is the vigour of the human imagina¬ tion which is responsible for the differences which emerge in our construction of experience, and these differences must, if regarded from the proper point of view, be taken as unreal in comparison with the one pure identity* Hegel is altogether 1 Kirtikar, 10. 202 COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA opposed to the abstraction which results in this annihilation of difference. The ultimate identity must be one which goes out into, and realizes itself through difference. As he puts it, ‘the Absolute is to be apprehended not as Substance but as Subject’, and he interprets this to mean that, as in the unity of our self- consciousness we can hold together a diversity of presentations, so in the Absolute the particularity of the world may persist without the suppression of difference, so long, at least, as we consider the relationship between unity and diversity in its static and not in its developmental aspect. But, on the other hand, in this statement Hegel puts himself alongside the Vedantist in respect of the centrality of thought in the universe. A Subject is essentially a thinking being, and it is therefore through thought alone that we reach penetration into real being and arrive at an identity comparable to that of the Vedantic formula, ‘That art Thou 5 . Indeed, so centrally important is thought in Hegel’s system that he has been accused, as is well known, of turning a Logic—or at least an Epistemology—into a Metaphysic, and reducing reality to a ‘bloodless ballet of categories’. Prof. Pringle-Pattison definitely accuses Hegelianism of ‘converting an identity of type into a numerical unity of existence’, 1 i.e. of passing from the con¬ sideration that all men think uniformly in their unifying pro¬ cesses of thought, to the idea that a unitary thinker thinks in all of them and that they and all their experiences are nothing but thoughts of this Universal Mind. He holds that the Hegelian position is ‘reached by hypostatizing the notion of self-con¬ sciousness and not by any progress from reality. There is, in fact, no bridge between this hypostatized conception and the world of real things and real men.’ 2 To a very considerable extent we may agree with this criticism, but, in passing, it may be noted that it rather leaves out of account the consideration that, after all, identity of type means something. Men do not think alike unless there is something in their nature which con¬ strains them to do so, and therefore the uniformity of their thought is significant of their place in the universe, and may be a fact of such importance as to be worthy of metaphysical status. 1 Hegelianism and Personality y 69. Ib. 171. AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT 203 But be this as it may, the parallel between Hegel’s conception of thought as fundamental and certain Vedantic ideas is sufficiently striking. As the Vedanta speaks of the creative forth-bursting force of the Word (and of the underlying thought) so Hegel speaks of the idea ‘freely letting itself go’ into the externality of space and time, and of the idea as ‘resolving to determine itself as an external Idea’. ‘The absolute freedom’, he says, ‘of the Idea consists in this, that it resolves to let the element of its particularity go forth freely from itself as Nature.’ 1 2 * Kirtikar compares this, as was indicated above, to the ‘Vedantic con¬ ception of Being proj ecting itself through its power called Maya! ? It resembles also the Upanishad passage, ‘Let me be many, let me go forth.’ It is doubtful, however, whether Hegel, in emphasizing the centrality of thought, would have reached the same abstractness in regard to thought as Sankara did. He would not, e.g., have abolished the distinction between thought and a thinker, but would rather have taken up the position of Ramanuja, and associated the universal thought with a universal thinker. In this he would have agreed with Prof. Pringle- Pattison when the latter says, ‘Thought exists only as the thought of a thinker; it must be centred somewhere. To thought per se we can attribute neither existence nor causal activity; and, this being so, it can have no place in existence as a theory of Being .’3 Neither would Hegel—ostensibly at least—have assigned to this pure identity of thought in which all things originate that position of aloofness and almost of superciliousness which we find in the rigorous monism of the Vedanta. There is with him at least no explicitly expressed idea that, when we turn to the particularity of the world, we are launching ourselves on a pro¬ cess of degradation. In fact, he says in his Philosophy of Religion that ‘spirit which does not appear, is not’. 4 He seeks to preserve the unity of significance and value even amidst the differences. Even though he desires to begin with the purely philosophical point of view and would almost say, as Caird points out, that we can only reach the infinite if we deny or cast loose from the 1 Werke, 414. Cf. Pringle-Pattison, Hegelianism and Personality , 112. 2 Kirtikar, 66. 3 Hegelianism and Personality, 78. 4 Vol. I. 26 (Speirs and Sanderson’s Trans.). 204 COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA finite, 1 yet he does not separate so abruptly as Sankara between lower and higher orders of knowledge. He recognizes the un¬ broken continuity between the scientific and the philosophical procedure, and holds, as Caird again points out in another connexion, that, £ if philosophy requires of the individual that he should lift himself into the pure ether of thought, on the other hand the individual has a right to demand of philo¬ sophy that it should let down a ladder on which he may ascend to this point of view; nay that it should show him that he already has this ladder in his own possession.’* Hegel’s aim is to show the reality as well as the rationality of the whole, and not merely the exclusive reality of pure undifferenced Being and the corre¬ sponding inferiority and illusoriness of particularity. Pure Being, with Hegel, instead of being the highest, is the lowest of the categories, and his polemic is continually directed against the folly of attempting to interpret the universe simply by such an inadequate category. He urges that we must interpret reality as an articulated system in which every part shall have its own proper and persistent place. Being must open out into Becom¬ ing, and the processes of nature must be given their place in the whole and regarded as calling for ever more and more adequate interpretations, until all the particulars are found to be unified under a supreme principle to which we find ourselves most akin in the highest development of human personality, and so break down the differences between the knower and the known and attain the completed ideal of knowledge. Yet though the Vedanta exhibits a much greater bias in favour of unity as opposed to difference, and Hegel arrives at a much fuller reconciliation of unity and difference than does Sankara, yet Hegel is not altogether free from bias in the same direction. Although he formally repudiates the idea of degrada¬ tion, yet we cannot help feeling that his almost purely intel- lectualistic attitude leads him into positions not far removed from those of the Vedantists, and that he is apt by logical exclusions to reach conclusions of an abstract character almost irreconcilable with actual experience and destructive of a serviceable attitude to the world in which we live. One of Hegel’s fundamental ideas is that of development; 1 Cf. Caird’s Hegel, 56. * Caird, Spinoza, 58. .. AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT >5 and, in considering this, the difficulty at once arises ^a^to whether all stages of the process are equally real. Hegehwas confronted with an awkward alternative, and whichever alterna- ,• tive he chose, he, with his intellectualistic presupposition, was in danger of depreciating the value of the individual. He found himself compelled to regard the individual either as an insignifi¬ cant part of a naturalistic cosmic process, or as losing reality altogether over against the sole reality of the Absolute in its final expression. On the one hand, in his reliance upon the centrality of thought alone, he found that this thought was apt to dissolve into negligible thinness in face of the developing actual, and leave us with nothing above the process itself. As Prof. Pringle- Pattison puts it: The metaphysical priority assigned to the logical system pales before the imperious reality of the senses. 51 The Absolute is being developed in the process, and therefore there is at any moment nothing higher than the stage already reached. To quote again from Prof. Pringle-Pattison: The circle is closed, finality is attained; the ideal is real and we see that it is so. 5 3 We seem committed almost to a deification of the actual, and to the acceptance of a system of naturalism and determinism. From this point of view a recent writer is not far wrong in describing Hegel 5 s ethics as a remorseless naturalism .3 As is the case in connexion with the doctrine of karma , to which the Vedanta in its less strictly philosophical moods gives its assent, we human beings are in the grasp of a pitiless process, and no freedom is left for us. Hegel may view the developing process more scientifically, but with him also the exclusion of freedom seems to be equally rigorous. Moreover, it is impos¬ sible to designate evil as evil, if every part of the developing pro¬ cess is equally real, and there are no marks of progress in the world. In such circumstances reforming zeal is out of place, and our only truly sensible procedure is to legalize custom and justify all existing institutions as well as the actual achievements of individual men. But surely for ethical health it is necessary, as one writer puts it, to Abstract from the concrete and actual humanity of our experience, from the real men and women ' Hegelianism, and Personality, 201. * Op. cit. 208. 3 Macintosh, Hegel , 211. 206 COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA whom we know, and know to be imperfect, to have failings as well as virtues and excellences of character, whom we love even in their weakness and perhaps even because of it, but whom we cannot worship or regard as the complete embodiment of the moral ideal’. 1 We cannot allow the ideal to lose itself in becom¬ ing identified with the actual, instead of being regarded as identi¬ fiable with the real, i.e. as the further truth of the actual which has not yet been attained. The other alternative with which Hegel is faced almost com¬ pels him to deny the reality of all stages in the process of development except the last. Here we find a close parallel between Hegel and the Vedanta, and an approach on the part of the former towards a doctrine of illusionism. Of course, there is a difference between the Vedantic view of the illusori¬ ness of all the variety of the world, and the particular form which this attitude assumes in connexion with the Hegelian doctrine of development. But some kind of depreciation of detailed experience seems inseparable from the intellectual point of view, qvtn when applied definitely and seriously to cosmic process; and the reason of this probably is that, when dominated by intellectualism, we are inclined to identify the motive of practical progress with the ideal of the attainment of truth. When, however, we are concerned mainly with the movement onwards from error to truth, we are apt to regard the stages of error as ipso facto swept out of existence as soon as truth has been attained.* We are compelled to regard every stage except the last as an inadequate and therefore unreal thought-con¬ struction. From a purely logical point of view, an unsatisfactory hypothesis fades away into unreality as soon as truth has been discovered; and when the logical conception controls us, we are apt to take up the same attitude towards the practical activities of our lives. We come, e.g., to regard inventions which have been improved upon and institutions of which the limitations have become obvious, as unreal in the same sense as a discarded hypothesis. But surely an engine which has been found to be out of date does not cease to be real in the same sense as an erroneous hypothesis; and, in general, the practical determina- 1 Seth, Ethical Principles, 409. 3 Of. the present writer’s Pantheism and the Value of Life, 563 ff. AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT 207 tions of our life-activity have a more abiding reality than the errors through which we pass on the way to the attainment of truth. In other words, it is not possible to apply a non-temporal and merely logical judgement to the contents of the temporal process without depriving these of reality and significance to an altogether illegitimate extent. It is not permissible to occupy in thought the highest point of view and then sweep back from that to the temporal with a depreciatory condemnation of the reality of our ordinary experience. And yet this is what Hegel often seems to do. He too fre¬ quently regards the various phases of the finite world and of human activity therein as merely a series of illusions. He is dominated by .‘the fearful power of the negative’, which always seems to treat reality as a negation of that which is actual at any stage in the process. Even the motive of our most serious struggles and highest aspirations is at times represented by him as a kind of illusion. ‘The consummation of the infinite End,’ he says, ‘therefore, consists merely in removing the illusion which makes it seem yet unaccomplished. The Good, the absolutely good, is eternally accomplishing itself in the world, and the result is that it needs not wait upon us, but is already by implication, as well as in full actuality, accomplished. This is the illusion under which we live} It alone supplies at the same time the actualizing force on which the interest of the world depends. In the course of its process, the Idea creates that illusion by setting an antithesis to confront itself, and its action consists in getting rid of the illusion which it has created. *■ The effect of such an attitude upon ethical and social endeavour can hardly be doubtful. It may indeed create in us a superficial optimism in that it enables us to be secure in the confidence that all is already accomplished and persuades us that we need not worry overmuch about the defects of temporal existence. We may be permitted by it to take up an attitude of practical indifference towards external happenings however dis¬ concerting these may be. We may deal with evil in a quick and superficially satisfactory manner by denying the total sphere in which it appears. We may get rid of uncomfortable details by bringing them under the category of the contingent, and thus i Italics mine. * Encyclopaedia, Sectionals. 208 COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA virtually refusing to recognize their reality. In fact all the diffi¬ culties of the actual may be got rid of by classifying them as untrue existences which, therefore, do not merit serious attention. Now this may be satisfactory so long as the philosophic mood persists, but when it weakens and the claims of the actual become insistent again, our placidity is apt to be disturbed, and we find ourselves without a refuge from the sorrow and sin of the world. And, when we are confronted with actual emergencies, our indiffe¬ rence will not longer be taken as a sign of philosophical elevation, but rather as a proof of ethical deficiency—an evidence of pitiless¬ ness in regard to the urgent needs of humanity. Once more, as we have had occasion to notice in connexion with the Vedanta, intellectualism is found to be insufficient for individual ethics or for the uplift of society; and we are inclined to agree to a certain extent with the verdict of the writer who exclaims with reference to Hegel somewhat bitterly, ‘To the strength of his logic—his mere logic—tears and blood and sins are negligible quantities.’ 1 But the point of comparison between Hegel and the VedantJ which is most important as regards ethics, and as we shall see also as regards religion, is the identity relation between man and God which is established in both systems. Sankara reaches identity with God by the way of abstraction, and Hegel by emphasis on a self-consciousness which turns out to be more divine than human, but in either case it is an identity which practically destroys the reality and freedom of the individual. Hegel, as we have seen, assigns much more importance to the diversity of the world than does Sankara, but it is not sufficient for true individualizing significance. For Hegel, individuality is after all of little value. The importance of the thinker is apt to be swallowed up in that of the thought, and ‘our minds are no better than shifting heaps of percepts, principles and syllo¬ gisms’. 3 Therefore it matters little what becomes of us so long as our thought persists; and the suggestion is not far away that even the desire to continue otherwise than in the immortality of our thought is a sign that we have reached only a compara¬ tively low philosophical level. To such an attitude Hegel was led by the course which his reasoning has taken. As has been so clearly pointed out by Prof. Pringle-Pattison, the system 1 Macintosh, op. cit. 14. 2 lb. 180. AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT 209 starts the Kantian synthetic unity of apperception, with the idea of consciousness as such, set over against the manifold of perception. The next step is to turn this unity into a meta¬ physical principle by universalizing it and identifying it with the divine self-consciousness. As Prof. Haldane puts it, there is in Hegel’s system ‘potential identity of man and God in a single subject of knowledge’. 1 This means that all that is left on the human side is the manifold and shifting content of per¬ ception ; and from such a position the transition is easy to regarding the human consciousness with all its variety of experi¬ ence as a mere thought of the divine thinker. Or we may put it more generally and say that the universe tends, in Prof. Pringle-Pattison s phrase, to shrink together into a logical pro¬ cess of which individuals are merely the foci’/* The individual is sacrificed to the universal, and, instead of hoping for personal immortality, has to be content with his persistence as a thought in the mind of God: he becomes, according to Lotze, a mere selfless state of the creator’. And as on this line of thought coalescence with the object known is regarded as the ideal of knowledge, so this idea of coalescence is applied to existences also. Identity expressed in association with the thought of absorption, however unsatisfying religiously this may be, comes to be conceived as the highest relationship between the soul and God; and the conclusions of Hegel in this respect may very well be placed alongside those of the Vedanta. In both systems it has been shown that, so long as we occupy a purely intellectual point of view, so long is it impossible to provide adequately for human personality or to find a fully satisfactory basis for the religious relationship. All that Hegel can say in reference to this is that ‘religion is the Divine Spirit’s knowledge of itself through the mediation of finite spirit. . . Religion is not a transaction of man, but is essentially the highest determination of the absolute idea itself. ’3 We may trace the same tendency to sacrifice the individual in much of the later thought which is based upon Hegel—the thought which according to Mr. Bertrand Russell follows the 1 Pathway to Reality, II. 169. 1 Hegelianism and Personality, 118. 3 Philosophy of Religion, I. 206. P , 2io COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA ‘classical tradition' and shows an inclination to make thought constitutive of reality instead of limiting it to the function of deciding between alternative possible interpretations of reality . 1 The result of the intellectualistic procedure in more recent philosophy also is that the thinker is of less importance than his thought, and the thought of the individual becomes a thought of the Absolute and the Universal. For Bosanquet the Absolute is the only true individual, and all so-called finite individuals are merely incomplete phases of the whole. He indeed indicates his approval of the idea that the main purpose of the universe is the ‘making of souls', and he quite fully appreciates the doctrine that souls differ, not merely as separate numerical entities, but because of their diversity of content. In this he seems to take a step towards a recognition of the concrete indi¬ vidual, but on the other hand he neutralizes any tendency in this direction by the emphasis which he lays upon the contents of the individual consciousness. He regards the contents as of far more importance than the container, and he draws un¬ warrantable conclusions from the consideration that in all the great experiences of life, in all our sharing of institutional and custom-born social organization, in all our aspirations after a more ideal state of our own selves or of society, we inevitably transcend the individual. With the purest and most elevated souls, this constantly happens, and according to him it is what ought to happen in all cases. As if any assertion of finite indi¬ viduality necessarily implied a selfish spirit, he speaks rather contemptuously of those who ‘try to divide up the unity and tell how much comes from “you” and how much from“God” T The contents of our personality ought to merge in the universal; our progress consists in an ever-nearer approach to this goal, and it should be a matter of regret and of conscious failure if we do not merge altogether. Our destiny, our being’s heart and home Is with infinitude, and only there. Our aim is to be an ‘element' in the Absolute; we should not claim even to be a ‘member’, lest the latter term should suggest too definitely a continuing individuality. 1 Cf. Preface to Bertrand Russell’s Our Knowledge of the External World . 2 Ci. What Religion Is^ 20. AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT 21 x Bradley also, while occasionally accommodating himself to the demands of ordinary experience, and admitting the criterion that ‘a result, if it fails to satisfy our whole nature, comes short of perfection 5 , and that 'if metaphysics is to stand, it must take account of all sides of our being 5 , 1 yet shows, on the whole, a definite inclination to sacrifice the individual. |‘Incompleteness, unrest and unsatisfied reality, are the lot of the finite. There is nothing which, to speak properly, is individual or perfect, except only the Absolute. 52 ‘The plurality of souls in the Absolute is, therefore, appearance and their existence is not genuine. 53 ;And again, the same attitude is taken up as regards the goal of endeavour, ‘The finite disappears in being accomplished. 5 4 He makes great use of the idea that the attainments of the individual are merely adjectival in relation to the Absolute, and thus seems almost content with the implication that the indi¬ vidual is nothing but a bundle of qualities. These are tempo¬ rarily conjoined in him, but do not belong to him, as it were, in his own right. They are merely held in trust for the Absolute, and, when the trust is fulfilled, the individual will surrender the qualities altogether for attachment to the Absolute. This will be his contribution, and in making this contribution the indi¬ vidual will fulfil his destiny. In such a position, however, there seems to lurk a contradiction. If the contribution is merely of qualities, these qualities, merely as such, might be supposed to be already possessed by the Absolute and therefore cannot be contributed. The idea of contribution has meaning, only if the individual can give also himself, in. whom the qualities can have that independence which alone can constitute them a gift in any proper sense of the term; for one cannot give as a gift* that which is already possessed by him to whom it is given. This difficulty, however, does not deter Bradley from reaching the conclusion that the true destiny of souls is absorption or transmutation into the Absolute. It is easy to see how such an attitude will empty the region of moral endeavour of much of its meaning. If there is no distinc¬ tion between us and the Absolute, and if, in respect of the Absolute, Bradley can say,.‘Nothing perfect, nothing genuinely real, can move; the Absolute has no seasons, but all at once 1 Appearance and Reality, 148. * lb, 246. 3 lb. 305. 4 lb. 419* 2 i 2 COMPARISONS BETWEEN THE VEDANTA bears its leaves, fruits and blossoms 5 ^ then the heart is taken out of the ethical struggle. In an earlier passage Bradley animad¬ verts upon the divorce between religion and morality with a view to showing that neither morality nor religion can be ultimate. He tells us that ‘if, flying from the discord, religion keeps its thoughts fixed upon harmony it tends to suffer once more. . . . The truth that devotion even to a finite object may lift us above moral laws, seduces religion into false and immoral perversions. Because for it all reality is, in one sense, good alike, every action may become completely indifferent. It idly dreams its life away in the quiet world of divine inanity, or, forced into action by chance desire, it may hallow every practice, however corrupt, by its empty spirit of devotion.’* The curious thing is that Bradley does not seem to see that the same consequences as are indicated in the last sentence may follow from his own posi¬ tion. If we are at best engrossing ourselves with a play of appearances, our final view of consummation will leave us without energy for the arduous stages of the process towards that consummation. As in the Vedanta, so with Bradley, the ethical level is found to be transcended, and goodness must be regarded as ‘a subordinate, and, therefore, a self-contradictory aspect of the universe’. 3 If everything is already accomplished, or if nothing that is accomplished has any prospect of con¬ tinuance, the life of the individual and of humanity is emptied of meaning, and, as we shall see, little place is left for any truly religious relationship. Very naturally did the almost pitiless intellectualism of Bosanquet and Bradley lead to a reaction in the direction of pluralism. But it does not seem necessary to pass in such extreme fashion from absorbing unity to inorganic particularity, and our concluding chapter will be occupied with an attempt to show that, while there are dangers associated with the ideal offered to us by the Vedanta system and philo¬ sophies broadly similar to it, it is possible also to conserve the religious value enshrined in the ideal and, perhaps, by certain modifications to enhance it. Hitherto we have been trying to trace the main tendencies of the Vedanta as these are reflected in its attitude to authority and within the scope of the doctrines of the two orders of 1 Appearance and Reality, 500. 3 Op* cit. 444. 3 lb. 420. AND MODERN PHILOSOPHICAL THOUGHT 213 knowledge, the notion of God both unqualified and qualified, the validity of external experience, and the place of the indi¬ vidual both in this life and that which is to come. We have found that the inclination of speculation has been strongly in a monistic direction and that it has been associated with a pre¬ dominantly intellectualistic point of view. We have seen that the same tendency is strongly marked in the philosophies of Spinoza, Hegel, Bradley, and Bosanquet, See., and that the most striking resultant might be described as, in general, a merging of the part in the whole, a sacrifice of the Many to the One, and oftheindividualtotheUniversal. Ourstudyof parallels between the Vedanta and other allied modes of thought has compelled us to recognize the principle of identity as their fundamental concep¬ tion. We are thus brought round once more to the point at which we left our main argument at the close of last chapter. There we found that the Vedantic basis for ethics which this principle affords, was decidedly insecure, and we have reached practically the same conclusion as regards the Hegelian school of thought. The underlying idea that the relationship between us and God is one of identity may indeed diminish the distance which seems to separate us from God and may deliver us from that coldness in our subjective attitude which a more external relationship might induce. Yet we have also become aware of undesirable consequence of various sorts. The finite has been absorbed in the Infinite, and a sufficient basis has not been left on which our individual personality may become effective. Intellectual- ism may save us from the bondage of the sense world and or dinar y desires, but it also presents a strong similarity to naturalism, in that, equally with the latter, it leaves us under the sway of determinism. It provides no sphere for the free creative activity of the spirit, and, if our experience is one with the experience of God, we come under the control of laws of thought which are not so much principles of our own action as superior determinations of that action, inasmuch as they are laws of the universal. The importance of the generalized point of view turns our attention away from the particular and thus tends to rob us of the vitalizing effect of action in reference to the particular. The result is a dream-like attitude to life, along with that sense of futility which attaches to dreams and the 214 THE VEDANTA AND MODERN THOUGHT consequent evaporation of ideals. The ethical life is thus robbed of the necessary energy for dealing with it, and because this life belongs essentially to the sphere of duality, we are required altogether to pass beyond it in reaching the goal of identity. The distinction between good and evil ceases to be the most urgent of contrasts, and presents itself not so much as a stimulus to effort as an opportunity for acquiescence. Tor, if we are one with God, and if in our search for universal Concepts we have risen above the movement of time and yet in our practical life have still got to live under the conditions of time, we are apt to satisfy our desire for eternity or timelessness by arresting defini¬ tively the movement of time and crystallizing the momentary into the permanent. ^ But when experience is thus theoretically conceptualized and practically made static, the ideas of further possibilities and progress are apt to disappear from it. We find ourselves confined to the charmed circle of the actual, occupied with perpetual analysis and re-analysis of given conditions and relations, and powerless to move forward to projects of reforma¬ tion. And from out the far distance there comes to us a vision which further robs our ideals of their effectiveness, for if we are one with God we are also complete in Him. Despite the warnings against ethical sluggishness which the moral intensity of certain writers on Vedantism compels them to emphasize, we yet can¬ not altogether escape from the conception that perfection on such presuppositions is not something to be attained in the long run, but something which we already possess. Almost inevitably the question arises in our minds as to why, if we have annihilated the temporal distance between ourselves and the goal’vve should any longer submit to the exhausting conditions of the race. But enough was said in our last chapter in reference to this point, and we are now left with the final question whether the same insecurity which we have discovered in respect of ethics will attach also to the only religious relationship for which the identity conception seems to leave room. We may focus our thoughts on the value of the identity principle by asking whether the relationship which emerges from it is sufficient for the purposes of religion, for, after all, the degree of religious satis¬ factoriness ought to furnish a supreme criterion of any system. This problem will occupy us in our concluding chapter. THE RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA, AND SOME CONCLUSIONS JT is probable that the applicability of such a criterion as we il- have just proposed, viz. the test of religious satisfactoriness, will be at once disputed,either on the ground that any test at all is superfluous or that this particular test is illegitimate and mis¬ leading. Those who assign the first reason for objection argue that the identity relationship is inevitable, and that therefore it is useless to discuss whether it is adequate or not. Such a rela¬ tion is said to be the ultimate position to which we must come when we fully analyse the conditions of knowledge, and is a necessary deduction from the fundamental assumption of ideal¬ ism. If an object is known only through thought, then the object itself is thought, and, when we are constrained to deal with thought alone, the identification of subject and object, and on broader lines, of the finite and the infinite, is the only form which our ideal of completed knowledge can take. The relation of subject and object, it is said, is that with which we start, and development will consist in overcoming the ‘otherness’, by means of the expansion or deeper knowledge of the subject. The western mind, which is inclined to idealism, will probably think more of expansion and the eastern of deepening, but the result in both cases is the same, and the ideal ought to be the same, viz. the identification of the subject and the object, and the entire removal of duality. As an Indian writer says: ‘One of the universally admitted maxims of Hindu philosophy is that the mind assumes the form of what it perceives, and, therefore, necessarily becomes what it perceives. 1 To know a thing is to become that thing, and, universally, to think properly of, or to know, the Infinite is to become the Infinite. Our aspiration in knowledge and in every spiritual activity is to Close with all we loved And all we flow from, soul in soul. True knowledge places us on a level with God, or, rather, makes us one with God. It is an ideal of knowledge which in western R. C* Bose, Hindu Philosophy, 169, zi 6 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA philosophy has come down from Aristotle, who holds that the only activity which can appropriately be ascribed to the Divine Being is the activity of the thinking mind, and that the charac¬ teristic of such thought is that ‘it becomes its object in the act of comprehending it’. For Spinoza the knowledge wherewith we know God is also the knowledge wherewith God knows himself, and the fundamental principle of Hegel is that in the highest thought we reach potential identity with God. We come across the same principle in the Mundaka Upanishad III. 2. 9, ‘He who knows Brahman, becomes Brahman’, and that such an ideal underlies the Vedantic conception of tat tvam asi is so obvious as to need no further comment. It is therefore asked why, in view of all this, we should take the trouble to apply the criterion of religious satisfaction which we have suggested. If we are faithfully to analyse the condi¬ tions of knowledge in their highest exercise, it is urged that no other relationship is possible except the relationship of identity, and that if this is not religiously satisfying, so much the worse for us. We have got to accept the inevitability of the facts of the case. In answer to this contention we may say simply that the epistemological assumption does not seem to us to be valid. We shall return to this point a few pages later, but in the meantime we may consider the position of those who object to the test of religious sufficiency on the ground that such a test is illegitimate and misleading. The reason which they give is that, even if we admit that a test may be applied, it is philosophy which must su pply the test and not religion. Religion is definitely on a lower level than philosophy; it is a stage through which the philosopher must pass, and failure to satisfy the needs of the lower is to be welcomed rather than deplored, inasmuch as unsatisfied need is a spur to the requisite progress from the lower to the higher. There are many instances in Vedantic teaching, and in Indian thought generally, of this depreciation of religion in favour of philosophy. Prof. Radhakrishnan thinks that if we try to remain at the religious level we shall be involved in an inextricable dilemma. Personality is essential to the religious relationship of worship, but yet personality is a limitation of the perfection SOME CONCLUSIONS 217 of the Absolute. Thus we are compelled to say that 'if God is perfect, religion is impossible. If God is imperfect, religion is ineffective’, the reason of the ineffectiveness being that 'we cannot have with a finite limited God the joy and peace, the assurance of victory and the confidence in the ultimate destiny of the universe’. 1 Prof. Radhakrishnan’s regret is noteworthy, as it implies an ideal of an effective religion which would seem to be indispensable for a completed attitude to the universe, but yet on the whole he extricates himself from the dilemma by holding that religion must be transcended. 'The end of religion’, he says, 'is the transcendence of religion,’ and again, 'Religious worship has to be accepted until the perfect condition is reached.’ 2 The main theme of an earlier work of his is to show that philosophical 'deviations from the “high road” of absolut¬ ism are all due to the “reign of religion in philosophy” ’. 3 It is true that later in the same book he says that'true religion and true philosophy will agree’, 4 but his vote would be in favour of a religion turned philosophy rather than in favour of a philo¬ sophy turned religion, and the reason of this would seem to be that a proper regard for the identity relation and for the con¬ sideration that, in order to know God, we must be God, does not admit of what is usually regarded as the religious attitude. Kirtikar is still more uncompromising as to the desirability of the dominance of philosophy over religion. Although he also leaves room for the ultimate identification of religion and philo¬ sophy, he is emphatic in his disregard of the ordinary religious consciousness. 'Ethics, morality and religious life’, he says, ‘admittedly belong to the sphere of relativity—to the world of the One and the Many,’ though they may be ‘as much necessary to the development and spiritual progress of man as the initial stages in the development of a child are to his attaining man¬ hood’. And he asks rather indignantly, Ms philosophic truth to be sacrificed lest its recognition might . „ . shake the very foundations of religion?’ 5 " 1 Radhakrishnan, I. 97. * lb. 235; italics mine. There seems to be a modification of this view in his book on The Hindu View of Life, which has just appeared, and in which he apparently suggests that religion has to do with a reality beyond all differences and is therefore ultimate. 3 Cf. The Reign of Religion in Contemporary Philosophy , Chapter VII. 4 lb. 22. 5 Kirtikar, 106 and 107. 218 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA It is obvious that, according to views of this kind, religion is given a place at all only on condition that it should be philo¬ sophically transformed, and should thus cease to be what we ordinarily regard as religious. The result will be of an exceed¬ ingly refined character, and of such a religion only a few chosen souls of a philosophical cast of mind will be capable, whilst the bulk of humanity by the very nature of the case will be excluded. Now it is noteworthy that this depreciation of the demands of religion takes place in connexion with adherence to the monistic Vedantic ideal of identity. We thus have an implicit admission that the conception does not satisfy ordinary religious require- ments; and, even though the additional suggestion be made that it does not matter very much whether the test succeeds or not, the admission of failure remains significant. But we may ask, Is it so immaterial that religious demands should remain unsatisfied by a conception taken to be meta¬ physically fundamental ? Despite the slightness of emphasis on this consideration which would seem to be indicated by the quotations just made, it would be a mistake to suppose that the Vedantists themselves are, in general, regardless of what they consider to be religious needs. We have seen how it was possible to say that no people on earth took religion so seriously as did the people of India. 1 The whole attitude of the Vedanta might be described as an attempt to do the work of religion, even though it be by means of a philosophy. Sankara has been described as ‘a great philosopher who fully grasped the necessity of religion to the world’,* and this by a writer who contends that the Vedanta was intended to be only a philosophy and not a religion. We have noticed both in Prof. Radhakrishnan and in Kirtikar a strong desire to identify religion and philo- sophy, which shows that, provided religion is kept in a proper relation to philosophy, they by no means wish that the religious test should be altogether abandoned. The former encourages himself with the consideration that ‘the monistic conception is 1 Cf. Deussen, S . V. 49; cf. also Heiler, Sunder Singh , p. an: 'India has been for centuries the land of religion. As hardly amongst any other people of the earth there is amongst the people of India a wonderfully strong sense of.the transcendental world and an earnest desire to sacrifice everything to this supersensible world.’ : Worsley, Concepts of Monism, 90. SOME CONCLUSIONS 2x9 also capable of developing the highest religious spirit’; 1 and the latter admits the principle that ‘the richness of an abstract con¬ ception depends upon its efficacy in awakening the religious consciousness in man’. 2 They would seem to be in almost com¬ plete agreement with the dictum of Hegel that philosophy only unfolds itself when it unfolds religion and in unfolding itself, it unfolds religion’. Why then are they in such difficulties ? Why have they either to depreciate religion as a test, or, if they admit it, why have they to distinguish so carefully between religion in general and philosophical religion, even while it has to be admitted almost despairingly that such a philosophical religion cannot be ‘for the bulk of humanity but only for the chosen few’? 3 Is it not because there is something essentially antagonistic between the identity principle which they cherish and the religious con¬ sciousness in general? They seem to be faced with the alterna¬ tive either of giving up the religious attitude, except in a very attenuated and almost purely philosophical form, or of giving up the principle. The reluctance of these very philosophers themselves to accept the first alternative encourages us to refuse the admission that the religious test is either illegitimate or misleading. We do not consider that the objections to the test are sufficiently convincing to lead to its abandonment. Religious value must be considered and not merely philosophical or religio-philosophical value. We are therefore back again at our central problem, as to whether the principle of identity offers such satisfaction to the human spirit in its highest development as to make it worthy of retention. Now it would be unfair to deny in any uncompromising way the religious value of the identity concept. It is indeed, as we have seen, reached through negation, both theoretical and practical, and through abstraction. But negation is, after all, the expression of a consciousness which is at the bottom of all religion, a refusal to indulge in a superficial optimism, and a recognition of the truth that ‘strait is the gate, and narrow is the way, which leadeth unto life 5 . And, on the other hand and more positively, identity is often regarded as the speculative basis of 1 Radhakrishnan, I. 98. / * Kirtikar, 24. 3 Worsley, op. cit. 16S. 220 . RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA that mystical consciousness which must be an element in every true form of religion. It is undoubtedly true that religion emerges from a mood of ‘divine discontent’ and is the indication of an insatiable quest. Whenever the religious consciousness becomes vividly and intensely awake, the soul is always inclined to say, ‘It is not here, it is not here—that which I seek’; and, in contrast to the urgency of the aspiration and the importance of its objective, the world of the actual is apt to assume a dream-like and illusive character. The Vedanta in its negations expresses very nearly the mood described by Wordsworth, when The gross and visible frame of things Relinquishes its hold upon the sense, Yea almost on the mind itself, and seems All unsubstantialized. The intensity of religious devotion expresses itself in a single- ness of aim which is intolerant of the variety of ordinary experi¬ ence, and conscious only of the inadequacy of that experience to reveal the ultimate Unity towards which the quest is so earnestly directed. If in such a mood the multiplicity of ordinary experience engenders a sense of confusion, perplexity, and mystery, it is perhaps natural that a solution of the problems should be sought, not in further examination of the ordinary, but in turning away from it, and assigning the mystery—now: become a source of attraction—to a detached Ultimate Being, in contact with whom, and in intuitive apprehension of whose nature, we may find that peace which the world cannot give—• as we reach that blessed mood, In which the burthen of the mystery, In which the heavy and the weary weight Of all this unintelligible world, Is lightened. 1 Perhaps occasionally it is true that the mood we have sought to suggest indicates that less worthy mental condition of lassitude or weariness of spirit which has moved a writer in Das Licht vom Osten to exclaim, ‘How tired must the Indian spirit have been of all Being, that no other deliverance was discovered by * Wordsworth, Tintern Abbey . SOME CONCLUSIONS 221 him.’ 1 It is necessary, as we shall see, that we should obtain some means of distinguishing between lower and higher mystical moods, but on the whole we should prefer to derive the prevail¬ ing mood not from lassitude but from a sense of the unreality of time, from a consciousness that we are passing beyond both spatial and temporal limitations, and that the permanence or eternity which we long for in religion is not some abode of bliss which we reach after the struggle of untold years, but something in which we may participate even here and now, just in so far as we realize the insignificance of the spatial and the temporal, and feed this mind of ours In a wise passiveness. 2 That it is not tubtc lassitude is shown by its association with the more volitional idea of self-denial. The Upanishads describe him who knows as him 4 who has no desires’, and it is felt in¬ tensely that the way to religious attainment lies through sacrifice and the emptying of self. We must ‘noughten all else that would keep us from God, in the spirit which T. E. Brown suggests in the following lines. But thou art all replete with very ‘thou’ And hast such shrewd activity That when He comes, He says, ‘This is enow Unto itself, ’tis better let it be: It is so small and full, There is no room for Me. 5 But the identity concept has value, not only in respect of the negations through which it is reached, but in regard also to the consummation which it indicates. It expresses undoubtedly an abhorrence of externality in religion. In these days we are somewhat weary of the idea of a God set at a distance from the world and from ourselves. Adeistic God is alien to our thoughts, and we demand that God should be conceived as in the world and especially as in us. It is felt that religion must be subjective or it is nothing at all. It must be ours , our own attitude. If God is to mean anything for us, He must be brought from out¬ side of us to the very inside, as it were, of our heart. And here the Vedantic formula, tat tvam asi y with its emphasis upon community of nature between the human and the divine, would * Op. tit. 92. - Wordsworth, Expostulation and Reply. 222 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA seem to promise satisfaction for our aspirations. It strengthens both our refusal to allow any longer that we are separate, self- centred, independent beings, and our claim that divinity is within us or that we are within the divine. God is all in all, and we are absorbed in the All—there is no longer any difference to disturb our religious contentment. 'From death to death goes he who sees plurality anywhere, 5 and we are encouraged to add that from life to life goes he who has abolished plurality and overthrown this mosaic wall of separation. It has been said that 'in middle life God becomes far less an object than an atmosphere 5 ; but such an experience surely may belong to all stages in the development of the soul. Thus we may freely admit the beauty and attractiveness of this religious conception of identity. It seems to represent the consummation of our religious yearning; and, even though we may be constrained to point out that it tends to embody the emotional resultant of normal religious relationship rather than to describe the religious relation itself, and that it throws into permanent metaphysical form what is a momentary, though oft-repeated, subjective and emotional experience, yet it cannot be denied that, for some minds, the identity relation with its mystical possibilities supports the intensest form of religion. And it may be said again that it is not by any means only the result of spiritual lassitude or even of exhaustion, but represents rather a positive and active spiritual awareness, 'the rest of infinite unrest 5 , as it has been called, an experience which is real, however wrongly conceived it may be through the influence of the particular thought-form under which it is subsumed. Even if it were on the whole more passive than we are willing to admit, it still, as Prof. Paterson says, 'remains a possibility that the God who giveth his beloved in sleep, could make some gifts in the Yoga-trance to those who sought Him therein with a pure and sincere heart 5 . 1 Perhaps also as Max Muller puts it, 'if it is true that “those also serve who only stand and wait 55 , then we may hope that even the quiet in the land are not so entirely useless as they appear to be 5 . 2 And surely even the most actively inclined religionist would hardly venture to evacuate of all meaning the classic description, so Vedantic in spirit, which 1 The Nature of Religion, 187. a Muller, S. S. 193. SOME CONCLUSIONS 223 Plotinus gives of mystical attainment: ‘It is a state in which you are your finite self no longer—in which the Divine essence is communicated to you. It is the liberation of your mind from its finite anxieties. Like only can comprehend like. When you cease to be finite, you become one with the Infinite. In the reduction of your soul to its simplest self, its Divine essence, you realize this Union, nay, this Identity.’ 1 Yet we still wonder whether this identity relation, despite all its beauty and spiritual satisfyingness, adequately represents the true conditions of spiritual communion and attainment. Some¬ thing fuller seems to be demanded. We cannot be altogether content, e.g., with such a phrase as ‘the reduction of your soul to its simplest self’. In such a phrase—which is typical—there seems to lurk a certain suggestion of abnormality, of negation beyond what is essentially necessary, and of too purely intel¬ lectual abstraction. We may ask whether in realizing and taking precautions against these dangers we may not reach a more adequate and more religiously valuable statement of the relation between ourselves and God. We have seen that the negation through which the identity is reached is to a certain extent commendable and necessary; but, if it is pressed too far, the accompanying advantages seem to be lost. Often it appears as if so much stress were laid upon the negation and abstractness of the means that they have infected with their emptiness the end which it* is sought to attain. We have already referred frequently to this negative process as applied to the external world, and we are now more immediately concerned with it as it affects the relation between the self and God. We discover a tendency to reduce both sides of the rela¬ tionship to their lowest terms, and thus to reach an identity of zeros so far as determinate qualities go. As regards anything more, we are left only with the affirmation of an indescribable experience, the product of an intuition alleged to be above the level of the intellect. It is by no means impossible to believe in the truth of such an experience, but we fail to see the necessity for such profound silence regarding its character, and it would be more satisfactory if it could be established, not in separation 1 Quoted in Kirtikar, 170. 224 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA from or in opposition to ordinary experience, but in organic connexion with it. Unless such an organic connexion can be shown, we cannot conceive of the identity relation being able to afford such a permanent basis as is necessary for religion. Denial must never be merely for the sake of denial; it must always have reference to a positive. It has its proper place only when something supremely valuable is apprehended in compari¬ son with which everything else is of lesser value or negligible, when there is discovered, as it has been put, c a reality so intense, so encompassing, so absorbing that beside it all other existences grow dim and at length fade into nothingness and illusion’. 1 But when the mind, as in excessive mysticism or asceticism, falls in love with denial for its own sake, and, faced with the difficulties of the actual, attempts to meet these only by way of negation; and, moreover, continues the same procedure with regard to the soul itself, the result cannot be satisfactory. When thought, devoted to abstract procedure, sets out upon its search for the ‘mythical Absolute’, for some unknowable substance hidden behind the qualities of the world, or some mysterious soul lurk¬ ing beneath all the processes of the mind, and when, failing in the quest, it is disposed to deny the reality of all the products of its exploring experiences, it may reach the conception of identity between that which has not been found in either direction of the search. But a result which is so closely and consciously asso¬ ciated with scepticism is hardly likely to perform adequately the function of removing scepticism, and yet this is surely one of the functions we naturally assign to religion—we expect it to give us at least some rock to which we may cling in the midst of our sea of doubt. It is significant in connexion with this line of thought that Sriharsa, a commentator of the Vedantic school who flourished about the end of the twelfth century, after dwell¬ ing constantly upon the contradictory character of appearances and the untrustworthiness of our faculties, reached a doctrine of Real Being which could be distinguished only with difficulty from a doctrine of the void. Now all healthy philosophy must begin with a certain amount of scepticism, and we must not try to minimize the difficulties of gaining a knowledge of the soul. As Oscar Wilde says: ‘To 1 Hibbert Journal) art. 'Centripetal Realism 5 , Oct. 1926. SOME CONCLUSIONS 225 recognize that the soul of a man is unknowable, is the ultimate achievement of wisdom. The final mystery is oneself. When one has weighed the sun in the balance and mapped out the seven heavens, star by star, there still remains oneself/ 1 And Bradley teaches over and over again that the subject in the end must be felt and it can never be perceived’. 2 The self is so deeply ourselves that one can hardly sound its depths. All this is true, but we exaggerate the difficulties if we persistently distrust our faculties, if we make, as it were, a cult of scepticism and by way of it hope to reach unity with real Being. Such procedure savours of abnormality and will be followed by some kind of retributory reaction. If we have found only vanity and illusion in the world, we have accustomed ourselves to the darkness, and one may come to expect that the self will be enveloped in the same darkness, in which we shall have to be content with blurred outlines and vague indeterminate forms of being. Or, to change the metaphor, we may make 4 a desert of the soul and call it peace’. 3 In this darkness or desert, this vagueness and indeterminate¬ ness, there lie great dangers for the soul filled with a haunting sense of emptiness. It may be tempted to the repose of death rather than of life. If such a result seems to follow from the depreciation of our faculties, which again is the consequence of disillusionment, then,as hinted above,the result may be desired, not out of a grim determination to reach truth, but simply from lassitude of spirit. As Prof. Paterson again says: ‘Repose may be the index of very different types of character, and the by¬ product of very different activities. It may be akin either to the peace of the saint or the sage, or to the placidity of the cow or the slumber of the tired horse. The pursuit of rest may be every whit as selfish as, and may entail even more injury to others than, the pursuit of wealth, and may have its roots in sheer indolence and cowardice.’ 4 Now in commenting upon the attractiveness of the identity ideal we have already indicated, as emphatically as possible, that it may correspond to the subjective ‘peace of the saint’, but the danger is that the abstractness of the result will not rule out 1 De Profundis, a Appearance and Reality, 108. 3 Cf. Prof; Paterson, The Nature of Religion, 205. • 4 lb. 205. ' Q ' 226 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA lower motives with sufficient strictness. If the result of the operation of both higher and lower motives is a featureless identity, we cannot from the result derive a criterion which will enable us to decide which type of motive has been operative. But this is unfortunate, and surely it is legitimate to demand that the result should have such positive character as will show it to be the outcome only of pure and elevated religious con¬ centration. We must be able to distinguish between the destinies of the^aint and the sluggard, and yet, in reference to an ideal which is largely described by negations, it is difficult to secure such differentiation. Thought that is abstract is always poor, and the poverty of our thought about the Absolute may make it impossible for us to refute the cynical reflection that unity with such an Absolute means that one lot happens to saint and slothful sinner alike. The course of our whole discussion has revealed a closely allied danger, also showing the religious inadequacy of the identity ideal. It encourages, not explicitly but implicitly, the use of lower categories. As Jeroboam, king of Israel, ‘made of the lowest of the people priests of the high places’, so do we make use of the lowest of our thoughts when we enter the shrine of the mysterious indescribable Reality of all things. The identity conception may seem to express the highest spiritual attainment of the soul, but the terms which it uses for expression are often based merely on physical analogies. A similar defect of course attaches to all use of language to express spiritual experiences, but the influence of the physical analogy seems to cling to the key-words of identity religion with more than average close¬ ness. ‘Absorption’, e.g., retains more of physical than of psychical association, and suggests something like the ‘plop’ of a raindrop in a pool of water. Bergson has drawn attention to this tendency of the intellect in abstract procedure, and has argued that the inadequacy of abstraction can be shown by the fact that the results of abstraction can be expressed only through spatial metaphors. What is psychical and vital cannot be reached by abstraction; but yet, as we make the attempt and think away one concrete determination after another, we come inevitably to the idea of illimitable spaces, filled only with emptiness, and are left with the feeling of our own loneliness SOME CONCLUSIONS 227 and helplessness and insignificance—we count for as little as a wave of the vast ocean or a speck of sand in the far-stretching desert. Even as we struggle upwards in our thought, we find it difficult to get away from the dominance of the physical. We may think of filled space rather than empty space, but the result is only the unsatisfactory conception of God and ourselves as forming ‘one block’ so to speak. Even biological categories yield only the idea of God as a vital principle, and ourselves as physically participating in his life. The point is that, if we insist on negation and depreciation of personality, we become prisoners of the lower categories of our thought, and these react so as to increase the depreciation and prevent fullness of relationship between us and God. We come to think ultimately in terms of material atoms and physical forces. Our relation to the universe is interpreted almost entirely in a quantitative manner. Not in our higher endowments of human character and personality do we realize our closeness to the divine, but rather in those of our faculties which are nearest to unconsciousness and our physical nature. No room is left for the uniqueness or the freedom of personality. We are swallowed up in God, and when we inquire who we are, no answer comes from out the silences of the boundless spaces. We are thus left without guidance, and into the emptiness, into the house of the intellect thus swept and garnished, undesir¬ able guests may enter. If our fundamental belief presents us with no deterring positive characters, we are at the mercy of arbitrary authority, superstition, and even of our own capri¬ cious invention. We have no criterion by which we may try the spirits and see whether they be of God. From our distrust of our faculties we draw also the conclusion that if nothing matters in the sense that nothing is reliable, anything may matter and be allowed to become dominant. Distrust of our faculties may produce a permanent and disconcerting mood of scepticism in which we despair of arriving at any universal standard. If a man is told that the deepest reality is without character and reached only through cohesion between the human and the divine in a featureless blank, or if he is told that in any case a satisfactory apprehension of it is impossible, then, seeing that he cannot exist in a mental and spiritual vacuum, he is apt to embrace any Q 2 228 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA theory or any object of devotion which lies to hand without scrutinizing it too closely. When the intellectual activity abandons its task through lack of content with which it may deal, or for sceptical reasons, it is apt to give way before an anti- intellectualistic reaction, and the house of the soul may be nlle with phantoms and extravagant products of unrestrained con¬ struction. 1 . - . r™ The further steps may be left to the influence of custom. I he mere habit of keeping a theory loosely in the mind tends to engender a certain liking for it. He who entertains it becomes loath to part with it, and the bigotry of superstition finds its opportunity. The pendulum swings over very easily, if not always in the same individual, at least in the same society, from agnosticism to credulity; and the transit has frequently been observed in the land where the philosophy of abstract identity is most naturalized. Bradley speaks of finding vanity and illusion in a world which is self-less and of then returning ‘to one’s self into congenial darkness and the equivocal consolation of some psychological monster’. 2 Sometimes, however, the consoling— and also terrifying—monsters may not be merely psychological hypostases, but exceedingly realistic projections of the imagina¬ tion which acquire a fictitious objectivity through the associa¬ tion of communal and traditional beliefs. Yet they do not satisfy with any permanent satisfaction even those who cherish them, for as has been said: ‘No religion can permanently take refuge in the glamour of vagueness and fluidity of conception and uncOrrelated elements.’ 3 Further, as we have had occasion to point out in connexion with our discussion of the ethical effects of the Vedanta, the identity conception may occasionally produce a mood approach¬ ing to subjective complacency or even conceit. Emphasis may be laid upon ourselves rather than upon God; we may take upon ourselves the burden of the universal consciousness, and seeing that this latter has been left destitute of content, it affords no defence against individual caprice. The individual may invest himself with the authority of the universal, and, intellectually 1 Of. the present writer’s Pantheism and the Value of Life , 299 ff. * Appearance and Reality , 120. 3 Angus, The Mystery Religions and Christianity , 263. * SOME CONCLUSIONS 229 and religiously, may do that which is right in his own eyes. An opportunity is thus afforded for that arbitrary perversion of the prophetic consciousness whereby a man claims specific illumina¬ tion and absolute authority for his own views and practices, and, in short, becomes a law unto himself in the realm of metaphysics and religion, like the ‘stateless man’ of Aristotle’s political con¬ ception. What Clutton Brock says of the ascetic is also true in a measure of such men. They ‘are the worst egoists of all, think¬ ing about nothing but their own souls, which means their own selves, living a life of inner conquest and adventure, which is all artificial . 1 Their interest, because they refuse it to external reality, is the more intensely concentrated on themselves; their very God to whom they incessantly pray, is but an idol made and set up within the temple of the self, and has no likeness to the real God, if there be one.’ 2 But surely, as another writer says: ‘The great individual is not the man who grows up in nearest approach to isolation; whoever does this will remain the nearest approach to a perfect idiot. The great individual is the man who is reacting to the greatest number of elements in Reality, the greatest variety of its aspects.’ 3 This brings us to the further consideration that identity which relies mainly upon negation is open to the charge of abnor¬ mality. We must apply this criticism with the greatest care. We must not take ourselves too seriously and regard ourselves as the type of the normal. But by normal we may be allowed to mean that which takes account of all aspects of experience, allows the fact of existence at least to create a presumption in favour of the continuance of that existence, and regards it as a justifiable assumption that the faculties we possess are meant to be used in an harmonious and systematic way, demanding that no one of them should be elevated at the expense of the rest. Normally we aim at the widest possible grasp of experience, and, if a negative movement in our thought seems necessary, we ask that it should be supplemented by a positive. As Prof. B. K. Shastri says, the truly religious man ‘pleads for a simple natural course of religion in every department of life, action, thought and emotion. . . . The ideal, the rational ideal, will first 1 Italics mine. * Essay on Religion, 86. 3 Bishop Temple, Christ us Veritas , 55. . . 230 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA spiritualize, will first rationalize, the whole scheme of life the so-called material and the non-material, and will, as a corollary to the truth thus established, vitalize and vivify the whole . . To work for human life, is to work for the whole world of life. 51 Now we do not think that the religious relationship we have been considering is able to satisfy this test. The element o agnosticism which is associated with it seems to be in conflict with the normal demands of the religious nature. It puts a man out of touch with the universe, in which he lives, and denies him an object whom he may invest with beauty and goodness, and thus worship and serve. And denial of the world leads to a denial of God or at least to the assertion of a merely character¬ less God, altogether unsatisfying. One abnormality leads to another. As Dr. Tagore suggests: ‘Flight from the world is flight from God. Flight from the world means an abrupt separation of the creature from the Creator.’ 1 The abnormality shows itself also in detachment of the individual from his society. It encourages him in the thought that the main object of his endeavour should be the salvation of his lonely soul. Within the soul, also, there is an abnormal elevation of the intellect over the other faculties, and this results in an abstract view of the self which empties it of all reality. In practice it leads to a non¬ evangelical indifference to the religious needs of the common people. When for religious purposes we rely entirely, or chiefly, upon the intellect, it must necessarily follow that the majority of men are excluded. A mediating view may of course be adopted, viz. that what does not satisfy the intellectual man may yet be good enough for the masses.- But such a view cannot be permanently held without weakening the religion of the multitude, or, for the sake of its preservation, inducing hypo¬ critical observance on the part of the intellectuals. It is curious how frequently a predominantly intellectual attitude has had associated with it a claim to a monopoly of divine truth and a jealous guarding of it from the intrusions of the vulgar. But such religious dualism is unfortunate whatever form it takes. Religious indifference which is born of intellectual superiority, i B. K. Shastri, 214, 225, 248. . 3 Quoted in Heiler, Christ and Indian Thought, 29. SOME CONCLUSIONS 231 or an assumption of this, does violence to our deepest desires both for ourselves and others. Those who are outside of the privileged class must of necessity feel that they are for ever excluded from the highest state of religious blessedness, whereas the noblest of those who are inside the favoured group will be depressed at the thought that others cannot share the privileges which they themselves enjoy. 1 2 But can we accept this abnormality of over-emphasis upon the intellect, with its indifference to evangelism, and the wider abnormality of which it forms a part, according to which it is assumed that ordinary experience is something to be got away from and that if we are to reach identity with God it will be by denial of the concrete wealth of our personality, by distrust or depression of the faculties which we possess, by deadening down or destruction of our desires, instead of by their sublima¬ tion? It seems impossible thus to reject the religious: validity of our ordinary activities in their fullness. Religious salvation means essentially the attainment of the health of the soul, the expansion of the normal powers of the whole man. ‘A free life’, as Prof. B. K. Shastri puts it, ‘ever seeks to be full in its freedom; free life and full life are indeed interchangeable terms.’* It is life and more life that we want, and not death, and our hearts will turn instinctively to such a Revealer as can proclaim that He came to give life and to give it more abundantly. Thus we come by many ways to the conclusion that the identity relationship between man and God, while it contains within itself much attractiveness and beauty and power, and while it describes significantly and valuably the emotional resultant of the true religious attitude, yet, because it has to lay aside so much, cannot adequately embody the fundamental 1 Prof. Wright has expressed himself vigorously on the relation between this attitude and religious adequacy. 4 If a religion*, he says, ‘becomes the private possession of a highly cultivated class, and is inaccessible in its higher insights to the masses of men, it will be bound ultimately to fail. The masses are in the majority, and the purer faith of the esoteric few will in turn become corrupted by the baser notions of the many. Only through active service of the needs of all can a religion permanently be successful in main¬ taining itself. And a religion cannot endure in its higher forms if it idly regards the lower form of religion in the nation with complacent toleration and makes no honest missionary effort to enlighten all and bring them up to higher levels.* (Philosophy of Religion, 84.) 2 B. K. Shastri, 326. 232 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA conditions of religious experience. It may turn out to be true that ‘the soul of man has not one centre but two; his own eternal entity—and God’. 1 Let us try to reduce the relationship to its simplest terms, and by analysis to discover its real nature. We prefer to proceed along the lines of the knowledge relationship, and also practical relationship, of subject and object. This seems to us inde¬ feasible; we cannot get beyond it, and do not require to get beyond it, even for the sake of the fullest religious attainment. Just as in the simplest act of knowledge a subject implies an object and an object a subject, so must it be in religion. God is our religious Object, and will for ever remain such; and we hold that this relationship can satisfy our most intense religious aspirations, not by way of identity, indeed, but by way of communion. Of course there are difficulties in the way of thinking of God as Object. We must beware of likening Him to the ordinary objects of sense, or of claiming that we can take up towards Him the same attitude of predominance or even of equality that we take up towards ordinary objects. But, on the other hand, a completed form of religion certainly does not demand either that the Subject should be fused with the Object or the Object with the Subject. However much more than a mere object God may be, and to whatever extent His reality may penetrate us or stretch beyond our comprehension, yet these considerations cannot destroy the distinction and yet connexion between us and Him which is involved in the subject-object relation. We must use our knowledge-giving faculties in a normal way; and in religion this means that we must regard God as an Object dis¬ tinct from ourselves, however similar He may be to us in nature, and however many bonds of connexion, closer than any we have yet comprehended, remain to be discovered and appropriated by us. - Thus in laying emphasis upon the subject-object relation we do not at all contradict our admission, made a few pages back, that in true religion God cannot remain a mere external object. Further—and this is much more important—we are quite 1 Cf. Hutton, Francis Thompson, 50. SOME CONCLUSIONS 233 aware that we shall be immediately confronted with the negative principle of Sankara, that we cannot ascribe subjective qualities to the object or objective qualities to the subject; and also with the positive central principle of the identity between the self within and the self without. It will set our position therefore in clearer light if we try to discover the real truth which underlies these principles. Surely they need not carry with them the denial of the relationship of subject and object. Rather are they intended to negate any abruptness of contrast, any utterly dis¬ concerting dualism. They emphasize rightly and impressively the spiritual kinship between us and God, and also between us and the world which God has made. The first principle has an effect dissolvent of differences, preventing us from setting the world over against us in permanent rigid outlines, from accept¬ ing it in its particular actuality, and so failing to reach its inner spiritual and friendly meaning, that meaning which proves its kinship with ourselves. In the same way it also prevents us from ‘concretizing’ and characterizing our own self with such definiteness as to encourage a distancing distinction between it and the universal Self. Thus the negative principle in its two¬ fold application prepares the way for the identification which take place according to the positive central principle, tat tvam asi. Now, though the explicit aim of this cautioning and recom¬ mendation may be the assertion of identity between ourselves and the world-principle, all that is effectively done, and all that ought to be done, is the breaking down of barriers and the re¬ moval of the feeling of alienation. ‘The saint’s rest’, as it has been said, ‘comes not from the discovery of anything hitherto unsuspected in himself, but rather because he has found that his spiritual nature is not wandering in an inhospitable universe, but has a home, and that in God. The rest lay not in what he would be, but in what One already was—an actual present fact.’ 1 But this does not mean that we are called upon to deny the subject-object relation; it only means that we are encouraged to discover and realize that there is a unity between ourselves and the whole which is as overwhelmingly certain as the reality of our individual self, and that no strangeness, no foreignness, can 1 Dunnin g y God and The Absolute, 234 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA continue to exist within that unity. We are asked to share with intensity in that sympathy which binds together the things of earth and the things of heaven, and also unites us with the rest of the universe which we inhabit. Religiously it ought to mean that the whole world is sacred for us, because it is the home of God, and it should suggest that we also are the temple of his spirit. But we do violence to the character of this intense con¬ sciousness of religious consummation when we compel it to constitute also the conditions under which it may arise, when we transform a feeling of closeness with the divine into an intellectual assertion of identity and thus press it into the service of a particular epistemological or metaphysical theory. It is surely, e.g., an extreme to say that, because our know¬ ledge cannot be complete until we reach the point of view of God, therefore complete knowledge involves the conclusion that God and we are one. God’s perfect knowledge—which may be taken as our regulative, but infinitely transcendent ideal in the realm of knowledge—does not mean that God takes us up into identity with Himself, but only that the relations between Him and us are perfectly understood. Even when perfectly understood, they do not cease to be real relations involving dis¬ tinguishable terms, and it does not follow that the two sides of the relation should fuse into one. Because God knows us per¬ fectly, it does not follow that we are God. Moreover, we should be careful not to interpret our regulative ideal wrongly. Be¬ cause the divine knowledge may be our ideal, this does not necessarily imply that perfect human knowledge must be ex¬ actly the same as perfect divine knowledge. Our knowledge may not be the knowledge wherewith God knows himself, but for all that it may be none the less valid. Even at its highest our completed knowledge is our own, not God’s. Thus the pre¬ supposition from which we try to reach an assertion of identity along this line of thought is not particularly satisfactory even as a starting-point, and does not legitimately reach the conclusion intended. It is not possible to establish the position, as a deduc¬ tion from the ideal requirements of knowledge, that, in order to know a thing, we must become that thing, or, in order to know God, we must become God. That ‘dread point of Intercourse’, however mysterious and unfathomable, in which the soul, tend- SOME CONCLUSIONS 235 ihg upwards, ‘holds, is upheld by God’, is still intercourse, and not fusion. . When we are faithful to the subject-object relationship, we find, on a direct analysis of experience, that it is quite unneces¬ sary and, indeed, impossible, to deny the reality of the subject or to merge that reality, irrecoverably, into a larger Reality. In fact it is just by descending into and affirming our own selves that we get our fundamental sense of reality. The Vedanta teaches this emphatically, but then goes on to assert that we know our own reality only as merging, or as merged, in the Universal Reality. It is this further step that we are unable to take; the self which gives us our hold upon reality is an inde¬ feasible self. It is through the consciousness of our individual self that we are able to extricate ourselves from that dreamlike mood which is apt to creep over us when we first become aware of the puzzling and often disconcerting character of our ex¬ perience. It is in the earnest quest of life which emerges in connexion with our self-activity that we establish a sense of true life, that we refuse to ‘take a dream for a truth’ and find that ‘The world and life’s too big to pass for a dream’. 1 Within our active experience we reach definiteness and concreteness which we cannot afterwards let go from us. As has been said, ‘Only when we lose sight of this connexion of thought with action, can we suppose ourselves able to rest content with appearances as a substitute for what really is.’ 2 And, invertedly, Kirtikar admits the truth of this principle when he says that ‘until the sense of “I” has completely disappeared, man has no right to deny the reality of the universe’, 3 which is equivalent to saying that, so long as the sense of‘I’ remains, man cannot deny the reality of the universe. We can prove illusion only theoretically or on paper. In our activity we are brought into contact with a real world and become growingly conscious of its reality as we deal with its problems. But this consciousness of the self, though indefeasible, is not isolating in its effects. As has been said: ‘There is something within us . . . which may be said to come into being only at the approach of God.... The deep and solving idea is that the final 1 Cf. Browning, Statue and the Bust and Fra Lippo LippL a Rogers, European and American Philosophy , 255* 3 Kirtikar, 4. 236 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA thing in the human soul is not that it is alone, but that it is in eternal fellowship; that we have each one of us one final com¬ panion, and that final companion is God. That man is a duality. That man is not a “thing in himself 55 . That he is a relationship. That his soul is, you might say, a state of tension between his conscious being and another. In short, that he lives and moves and has his being in God. The unit of the human race is not a person, it is that person’s communion with another. 51 In the real essence of ourselves, especially in the real activity of our¬ selves, we reach beyond ourselves, and we do not do this in any spirit of annexation. Because we have found so much of im¬ portance in the depths of ourselves, and because we have recognized our essential kinship with the universal, we do not claim.to be the universal. The fundamental significance of the self within us does not warrant us in dragging all reality within our subjectivity. Rather in our activity, especially in its noblest aspirations, do we become conscious of outlets to a wider reality. 'Having renounced the unworthy reality, I ought to replace it by what is worthy of existence. 5 % In our moral striving we are conscious of setting up an ideal, but at the same time we know that this is not our own construction, but that we have drawn it from a reality beyond ourselves. As Suso says, 'He who finds the inward in the outward is a more spiritual man than he who can only find the inward in the inward. 5 3 What we supremely value is not merely ourselves; the good for which we strive is part of the good of the universe. We are humbly and reverently conscious of the great Other from whom our inspira¬ tion is derived. 'Self-realization 5 , as one writer has it, must be balanced, not with a pantheistic, but with a transcendent con¬ ception of God, for only thus can a man be saved from the worship of self to the worship of God . 5 4 And as our intensest subjective activity is sublimated into worship, we are conscious of the Object of our worship, not as ourselves, nor as the projected image of ourselves, but as some¬ thing beyond ourselves, immensely attractive and immensely elevating. The essence of worship is the love of God, and love 1 Dr. Hutton, Francis Thompson, 108. 3 Solovyof, The Justification of the GW, 245. 3 Quoted in Hibbert Journal, Jan. 1925. 4 G. Gardiner, Vision and Vesture , 127. SOME CONCLUSIONS 237 is not merely a subjective feeling. It is not directed towards our own selves. It is directed outwards far more than inwards, to¬ wards that which is supremely valuable in the universe and in ourselves, but is never merely ourselves, seen through the haze of self-esteem rising from the mists of complacency. And so in worship we pass, naturally and inevitably, from the reality of the self to the reality of the Divine Object, recognizing once again, and now especially in the sphere of religion, the fundamental character of the subject-object relation. The love that is worship and the worship that is love are alike impossible except as a relation between two terms, and the relation cannot be maintained if these are fused together into an identity. In whatever way the inclination to this fusion manifests itself, it renders true worship impossible. If the stress falls upon our¬ selves, it is obvious that we cannot make ourselves into an object of worship. If we allow the stress to fall upon the object almost exclusively, and permit ourselves to be merged in the object of our adoration, it is equally obvious that we cannot offer the worship, for we have left no foundation in ourselves upon which we may set up our altars. Worship essentially implies a going beyond ourselves in devotion towards and adoration of a Divine Being from whom we all the while distinguish ourselves. The adequate relationship can be established only if we approach it with a vivid consciousness of the reality both of ourselves and God. Subject and Object must both be given their rights in religion as elsewhere. But in speaking of the rights of the individual in this connexion we must beware of the danger of irreverence, of which danger the Vedanta has done so much to warn us. As already hinted, we cannot claim for ourselves greater importance than, or even equal importance with, the religious Object. While our relation to God must be one of co-operation and confident response, it must also be one of humility. The greater importance must be attached to the Object. Prof. Paterson tells us that it must be ‘taken for granted by all who believe religion to be a reality that God is the all-important member of the sacred association, and that there has been a contribution from the divine side which makes the religious relationship immeasurably to surpass, both in content and in promise, the most intimate and enriching 238 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA form of human union’.* God is above us and beyond us, and in our approach to Him we must lay our hands upon our mouths and keep silence. It is here that we reach the truth of the Vedantic emphasis upon the uselessness of our ordinary cate¬ gories of thought and understand the inner meaning of negation, asceticism, and mystical self-forgetfulness and abandonment. We approach God by the way of a sense of the insufficiency of the finite self, as well as by way of a confidence m our limited self-sufficiency. We are dependent as well as independent, and our dependence is greater than our independence. . It is here also that we reach the truth of the Vedantic reliance upon authority which has seemed to some to be pressed to extreme lengths. For if we believe in the greater and the abso¬ lute Value of God, and yet believe also in his kinship to us, we are bound to take up the position of learners by slow degrees of the mysteries of his divine nature and purposes. We come also to the further confidence that in the course of the world’s history God has not left himself without a witness, and that his revela¬ tions may be made through others as well as through ourselves, a collective authority thus being constituted which we neglect only at our great loss and peril. In learning this lesson of humility we may begin to understand the truth of that saying of Jesus Christ that those who would enter the Kingdom of Heaven must become as little children. And as we realize that we are not sufficient unto ourselves, we shall be the more ready to place our confidence in those whom He has sent to be the prophets and teachers of the world, and pre-eminently, it may be, to believe in Him who came forth from God, and m whom are ‘hid all the treasures of wisdom and knowledge’. There is much truth in the lines of T. E. Brown. If thou wouldst empty all thyself of self Like to a shell dishabited, Then might he find thee on the ocean shelf And say, ‘This is not dead’, And fill thee with himself instead. And we must not forget the complementary aspect of the truth. Again the negative must always be in relation to a positive. It is not because of the emptiness of God, or even because of his 1 Paterson, Nature of Religion, 448. SOME CONCLUSIONS 239 indescribableness,butbecauseof his fullness of qualities and the richness of his glory that we bow ourselves in adoration. But while we are on our guard against irreverence and self- assertion, we must also beware of another danger in this con¬ nexion, if we place excessive emphasis on the transcendence of God. We must not carry humility and reverence to such an extreme as spiritually to grovel in the dust before the majesty of God. The faculties which we possess have after all been given us by God. Some one has said that ‘genius in man is the Godhead in distribution’; and ‘ what is true of genius is also true 0 f more ordinary qualifications’. 1 The Holy Spirit may mean the collective and Godward aspect of the human soul as God made it, and before man marred it, and the continuing help of the Holy Spirit may symbolize the idea that the channel of communication between God and man has never all down through the ages been altogether closed, although man may often have behaved and acted as if he were alone in a lonely universe. Man has in his nature and set right within his heart an indefeasible power to attain to God, and this power should be his glory and his confidence. The summons to the old Hebrew prophet was, ‘Son of man, stand upon thy feet’; and the voice may be listened to as a challenge to all humanity. Although their idea was not so much to cultivate humility as to prepare the way for absorption, the danger is linked with that depreciation of human personality which has so often suggested itself in connexion with Vedantic teachers. They have increased the danger by their over-emphasis upon negation, but perhaps they have also suggested a way of guard¬ ing against it. We may develop further their teaching as to the community of nature between us and God, and in such a way as to provide the warning rather than increase the danger. Through this community of nature we possess interpretative fights in the universe; we are organic to the universe, as Prof. Pringle-Pattison has so often and impressively told us. We can claim to understand something of the nature of the Divine Object just because He is not alien to us. Our typical actions, both intellectual and practical, are significant of the nature of the Absolute. Our thought-procedure, e.g., is one of the 1 -W. Robertson Nicoll, People and Books, z io. 240 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA constituent elements in reality-an aspect of the truth which we do not think has been sufficiently recognized in Prof. Pringle- Pattison’s otherwise extremely valuable criticism of the Hegelian transformation of a logic into a metaphysic. Principal Oman puts the matter thus: ‘The more we have stood upon our own feet, and thought and felt and acted for ourselves, the more the whole universe has responded to us. , Our interpretations must be based both on our humility and our confidence. Because of our humility we shall think of God as infinitely transcending us in resources, as corresponding only to our best and not to our worst, and as ready to supply the deficiencies indicated in our intellectual and practical limita¬ tions. But, because of our confidence, we feel that we may regard the elements of our personality as revealing the nature of God, that we may proceed from the best within to the best without. r And so, discriminatingly and humbly, we make use of our own nature in order that through it we may know God. We demand liberty for comprehensive interpretation, encouraged thereto even by an intellectualist like Bradley, who admits that ‘if the main tendencies of our nature do- not reach consumma¬ tion in the Absolute, we cannot believe that we have attained to perfection and truth’. 2 We cannot be content with thinking of God, after the manner of the Vedantists of Sankara s school, as merely intelligence or self-luminousness. Rather do we, follow¬ ing Ramanuja, tend to think of him as the abode of all auspicious qualities, or—in more modern and more comprehensive phrase -as the home of all values. Especially do we think it natural and necessary to carry with us into the region of the Absolute, our good—our actually accomplished good, and our most un¬ fettered anticipations of it. We claim interpretative rights for our ideals as well as for our attainments. The exceeding naturalness of this procedure of our thought is illustrated strik¬ ingly by Clutton Brock when he says, ‘The word provoked by evil is “why ?”, but that word is never provoked by good. 3 .* S dmce ' Rdi 8 i 0 n /Zi£f% ^C&bTsdovyof, The Justification of the C^o^24S^Tmthwhichis thinkable only and not^aF^^truth which 6861111:116 Wh016 ° f Uf ^ iS ^^ ", 7- SOME CONCLUSIONS 241 This illuminating good we seek to comprehend in all its variety, and, combining it with other qualities both intellectual and aesthetic, we present it before our worshipping spirits in the unity of a Personality whom we reverence as Divine. One of the most impressive philosophies of the nineteenth century has. taught us that perfect personality is in God only, 1 and this apprehension of the essential character of cosmic reality corre¬ sponds to the felt need of humanity all down through the ages; for, as Renan puts it, ‘Humanity seeks the idea, but it seeks it in a person and not in an abstraction.’ a And the thought of the French writer is an echo of the cry heard in an eastern land from the lips of Tulsidas, ‘The worship of the impersonal laid no hold upon my-heart.’ We refuse to be content with an absolute blank, and we fill up the emptiness with qualities drawn from our Own personality, having a not unwarrantable confidence that these qualities are divine; for personality is our most valuable possession, and we hold fast to a belief in the ultimate identity of value and existence. And in taking up this attitude to God, we think of Him above all as active and of ‘the whole course of things as the expression of his unceasing will’. 3 Prof. K. Shastri argues that even Sankara would attribute activity to God, to the underlying real Self, and that it is only change which he wishes to deny, Prof. Shastri says: ‘Whenever Sankara denies agency to the self, it is always the passive agency (if such a term can be used) of the empirical self. Sankara never denies anywhere the free active agency of the real Self.’ 4 But apart from the difficulty of recon¬ ciling the conceptions of activity and changelessness, we have already seen reason to think that it would be difficult for Prof. Shastri to establish such a position and that the prevailing tendency of the Vedanta is almost to overlook this active aspect. In any case it is pure or theoretical activity which Prof. Shastri has in view in his particular argument rather than concretizing activity having purposeful results. But, notwithstanding this, we think that Prof. Shastri is not wholly wrong if we take into account the spirit and implications of the terms used rather than the explicit utterances in which these terms are embodied. For 1 Of. Lotze, Philosophy of Religion. * Marcus Aurelius, 582. 3 Cf. Wright, Philosophy of Religion, 432. 4 K. Shastri, 60. ' ' R 242 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA the unfolding of our conception of the divine^ activity it is certainly possible to borrow terms from the Vedanta as well as from the Gospel of St. John. We may, e.g., consider the divine energy as bursting out of the charmed circle of mere thought through the Word, the Logos, the sabda, uttered eternally as well as in time. Through the Word of his Power, God makes the primary transition from His thought to actuality. It reaches embodiment first of all in sound—a mere vagueness, but, inas¬ much as it is the vehicle of possible ‘commands’, containing within it the germs of the idea of purposiveness. It passes to greater definiteness in the concrete existences of nature and of history, revealing moral characteristics, and indicating progress, in the greatness of promise for humanity when the Woi d be¬ came flesh’, and in potentiality for all men in the power given to them ‘to become Sons of God’. ... As we tkiuk of God along the lines of what is best within us and in the light of historic revelations of his nature, we regard the divine activity as dominated by love. This is in accordance with our principle; for it is the love of God which expresses most fully the truth of the subject-object relation in religion, as well as the superior importance of the Object, and at the same time the Vedantic truth of the nearness of God to men in the affinity of nature and the incidence of grace. It is love which saves us from the dangers of the identity conception, and by establishing both terms of the relation, gives substance to the idea of communion between God and man and prevents it from being a mere sentimental human yearning. And as applied to God, love means the outflowing activity of God, in trustfulness, towards a world which He has made, and expresses our belief that He gives to the world such reality that He would not be God without it and without satisfying its needs. He looks upon the particular as a trustee for the whole, and Himself makes possible the fulfilment of the trust. The conception seems to emerge from a metaphysical necessity; and even Bradley, with all his intellectualistic tendency, admits its validity as a deduction from an adequate conception of the universe. ‘If other things remain equal,’ he says, ‘a definite place in, and connexion with, the temporal system gives increase of reality. Not to appear at all in the series of time, not to SOME CONCLUSIONS 243 exhibit one’s nature in the field of existence, is to be false and unreal. And to be more true, and to be more real, is, in some way or other, to be more manifest outwardly. For the truer is always the wider. There is a fair presumption that any truth which cannot be exhibited at work, is for the most part untrue.’ 1 The same idea is expressed by a recent writer in words which provide an association with, and a contrast to, the Yedantic con¬ ception, ‘All may be maya until one has found the Central Reality; after that, reality, meaning, value, radiate to the last electron and the remotest star, but above all and in a far higher degree, to “the least of these my brethren”.’ 2 Now this expansion of reality, this concern of the centre for the circumference, with an almost humanistic interest in the individuals between the centre and the circumference, seems to be best expressed through the conception of Divine Love. We should stress the connexion between the divine love and activity. We should not think of God as simply the attractive object or magnet for human love, but as Himself descending in the service and expression of His own personality, streaming outwards in His loving-kindness, annihilating the separating distance between the throne of His infinity and the turmoil of existence. Under such a conception it is impossible for us to entertain the idea of God as depreciating the world or treating it as a mere dream or system of appearances. Philosophy (as represented in a Bradley) and religious needs unite in helping us to regard the world as the real condition of the existence of real spirits and the possible environment of an Incarnation of the Divine, both in humanity and in a very special sense. Here, it seems to us, we approach the metaphysical idea which may be taken to underly that central text of Christianity, ‘God so loved the world that He gave His only begotten Son—implying an utter trust of the Divine in the world-conditions of humanity and in humanity itself. For religious purposes this metaphysically justified trust in humanity is of the utmost importance. It arises from a full acceptance of the principle—enunciated by Lotze and accepted by Ward—that creation has little meaning unless it means the 1 Appearance and Reality , 381. % Hibbert Journal, art. ‘Centripetal Realism", Oct. 1926. 244 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA creation of creators; and implies a full appreciation of the significance of the individual both for time and for eternity, as well as a refusal to merge him, undistinguished, in the divine existence or to treat him as a mere phase of the divine conscious ness. We feel, with Bishop Temple, that it is impossible that things or persons should wholly constitute one another. This principle also involves a recognition of the importance o^history or in other words, a realization that the activities of individuals in'relation to one another have had value m the past and have had consequences continuing their effectiveness to the present and into the future, which will be accepted by God as con¬ tributing to the unfolding of His purposes. Nor do wethinkit illegitimate to pass from the idea of general benevolent activity of God to special expression of His mercy. This is simply to unfold the implication of the idea of com¬ munion between God and man and to press further pedan¬ tic idea of divine grace and pity, talcing these ideas out ° f the region of mere contemplation of the miseries of man, out of the region of sentimental compassion, and placing them as active forces in the region of the actual. As Bradley says, ‘We must not admit the possibility of an Absolute, perfect m apprehen- Sn, yet resting tranquilly in pain.- The Divine Love aims at communion, but, seeing that men are not perfect, and that misusing their freedom, they have gone far astray in the paths rf error and of sin, the love of God has to deal with the conse- ouent suffering and evil; and communion can come only as a result of restoration. In its idea of the unity of the human and the divine the Vedanta suggests conditions for redemption; why should not these conditions be constrained by concrete Divme activity to yield up the possibilities that are m them. In the Gita we find the idea that God incarnates Himself again and again for. the benefit of suffering and sinning humanity; why should not this idea of redemption be dissociated from some¬ what meaningless repetition and unreality, and dignified by- connexion with a continuous, unitary, and actualized divine purposefulness? An Indian writer says ‘Krishna s incarnation fs a P camouflage, but it is for the well-being of the world. Christus Veritas , 57* 3 Appearance and Reality , 158 * 3 B. K. Shastri, 393* SOME CONCLUSIONS 245 Courtesy to the adherents of another faith would not permit us deliberately to select such a term, but the important point is the connexion in the mind of this writer between camouflage and the well-being of the world. Such a connexion hardly seems to provide a solid basis for religious faith, especially if it is possible, as we have tried to show, that the camouflage may be trans¬ formed into an actuality. We would press the idea of redemp¬ tion back into the very heart of reality, and would take the fullest meaning out of an earlier statement of the same writer that ‘every item of creation is really an item in a great scheme of God’s self-sacrifice for me and for the world 5 . 1 The highest soul of the universe can be, nay, has been, proved to be not indifferent to men, but takes their weakness up into his strength, and sends downwards his strength and his purity to redeem them from their sinfulness. Those who enter most fully into the spirit of the Divine sacrifice are so inspired by it that they desire to reproduce it in that evangelism which by word and deed will proclaim the good news of salvation to others—even to the most unlikely, the degraded, and the outcast, ‘the least of these my brethren 5 , and will accompany their words by service which will bring nearer the redemption of mankind. As Prof. Radhakrishnan says, ‘The great souls of the world address themselves to the task of rousing the divine possibilities in the publicans and the sinners 5 , 3 and his thought corresponds to that of the writer we have just been quoting from: ‘Individual life engaged in sacrifice helps in the fulfilment of self and the world. 5 3 This represents a great advance on the earlier attitude of the commentator Madhusudan, who in speaking of ‘the vice which enters so largely into the composition of human society 5 , says, ‘the least that one can do is entire indifference. If he can help to cure ... it is sacrifice of a superior kind, but generally •indifference is the best attitude to maintain. 54 Vedantism in relation to those aspects we have just been con¬ sidering does not seem to satisfy those of its adherents who are most affected by modern influences. In general there seems to be a striking parallel between the attitude of St. Augustine to the philosophical teaching of his day and the possible attitude 1 lb. 195. 3 B. K. Shastri, 197. 3 The Hindu View of Life, 71. 4 Quoted in K. Shastri, 168. 24 6 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA_ of many modem thinkers in India and elsewhere to the Vedantic view of life. Speaking of the Platonic books in Book VII, Chapter 9, of his Confessions, St. Augustine says: ‘Therein I found that “in the beginning was the Word and the Word was with God, and the Word was God”, and that God, the Word of God, is the “true light that lighteth every man that cometh into the world”. But that “He came unto his own”,—this I found not there. Also I found that God the Word “was born, not of flesh nor of blood,nor of the will of man,but of God”. But that “the Word was made flesh and dwelt among us”, this I found not there. I could discover in these books, though it was expressed in other and in varying phrases, that “the Son was in the form of the Father and thought it not robbery to be equal with God”, because by nature He was that same substance. But that “He emptied Himself, taking upon Him the form of a servant, and became obedient unto death, even the death of the Cross”—this those books do not contain. . . For thou hast hidden these things from the wise, and revealed them unto babes, that they that labour and are heavy laden might come unto Him, and He might refresh them, because He is meek and lowly in heart, and the meek He guideth in judgement, and the gentle He teacheth His ways, looking upon our lowliness and troubles, and forgiving all our sins.V The Vedanta will afford such satisfaction to the human spirit as it can give, mainly in the intellectual and practical sphere, but concretely and practically, in the realm of history and ethics, it seems to be too detached from the need of men. It moves in worlds of its own not realized by ordinary humanity; it does not* base itself on reality and from its comprehension of reality derive strength for the deliverance of men, nor does it view the problems of humanity with that steady gaze which is necessary if a solution is to be discovered. It is so completely baffled by speculative hindrances that it is unready for the practical crises; a denial of reality does not pre-. dispose our minds to reform. Just because it takes the way of action as well as the way of thought, Christianity is not in like measure prevented from getting into touch with actuality. Ideally—though those who name the name of Christ have so frequently failed to express His spirit—Christianity comes nearer to the concrete problems of life and provides more fully for relief from the sins and sufferings of men. But while it is m SOME CONCLUSIONS 247 touch with the actual, it is not forgetful of the possible, it is not content with a finished and limited vision, but one of its central beliefs is that 'eye hath not seen nor ear heard, neither hath entered into the heart of man what God hath prepared for them which love Him’. It doth not yet appear what we shall be, but certainly our vision of the future under the guidance of Chris¬ tianity does not include the gradual fading away of the outlines of our personality into the being of God. The nearer we ap¬ proach to God, the steadier will be the concentration of our gaze and the more rapt will be our communion, but we neither hope nor desire that we shall become God. Yet in this connecting of the possible and the actual, in this linking of human potentiality with divine purposefulness, in the proclamation of the possibility, and the hastening through service of its realization, Christianity seems - to continue and make available and valid for all men the central teaching of the Vedanta. The great and fundamental truth of the latter—the tat tvam asi —'That art Thou'—finds its counterpart and its completion in the message of the New Testament, symbolized in the name given to Him whom we believe to be at once Son of God and Son of Man. The tat tvam asi seems like a question sent out by abstract thought into vague immensity, and in the name Immanuel, God with us, there comes back an answer which satisfies also the longing of our hearts. Is it too much to believe that in Christ India may find the goal of her searching, the satis¬ faction of her desire to realize the nearness of God, a conscious¬ ness of which is fundamental in the t^ching of the Vedanta? Thus there would seem to be a remarkable affinity between the Vedanta and much Christian thought and life, and a not irrational basis for the idea that the Vedanta naturally reaches forwards towards, and welcomes, the transformation which may be wrought by the presentation of essential, and not merely conventional, Christianity. But in this close relating of Chris¬ tianity and Vedantism there is need of great care. Premature synthesis and sentimental breaking down of distinctions do more harm than good. The Vedanta is not Christianity, and never will be—simply as the Vedanta; but it is a very definite prepara¬ tion for it; not a preparation for the acceptance of the particular dogmatic and institutional forms in which Christianity has often 2 4 8 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA been presented, but for the Christ Himself. For we who belong to nominally Christian communities cannot pretend that Christ has not frequently been despised and rejected by us, neither can we claim that we have allowed Him to appeal in all His essential attractiveness to the Indian mind and heart. But we believe and we are strengthened in our belief by a study of the Vedanta _that when he does so appeal in simplicity and .directness, He will in India draw the hearts of all men unto Him, and reveal Himself as the Desire of the nation. We ought to recognize more fully than we have as yet done the service which Indian thought may render in the interpreta¬ tion of Christianity. As Max Muller said long ago, ‘Vedantic teachings may bring us very near to the earliest Christian philosophy, and help us to understand it, as it was understood by the great thinkers of Alexandria’. 1 And what is true in reference to the earliest Christian thought ought to be still more true of the latest. The thought of India is influencing more and more pervasively the thought of those who are occu¬ pied with the unfolding of the truth that is enshrined in Chris¬ tianity, and we should not be unready or unwilling to acknow¬ ledge the debt. We have a Saviour whom we believe to be the Saviour of the world; and all men must help forward, in unity of aim and accomplishment, the understanding of Him. Further, we need to appreciate more fully than we have yet done the general religious aptitude of India. In the very denials of her thought, in the very intensity of her ascetic abnegation, she has expressed something of the deepest need of the human soul, that sense of loneliness and of mystery and of helplessness over against the immensity of the universe, which are a prepara¬ tion for the overwhelming Presence of God. And as regards developments of the religious consciousness which we may look for in the future there is a good deal of truth in the words of Prof. Vasvani of Bombay: ‘The West will come to the East to learn its age-long wisdom, in order to develop its own mystical sense, to look upon Nature no longer merely as a field of scientific experiment, but as the sanctuary of the Spirit, to exer¬ cise itself in meditation so as to grasp the spirit of idealism and realize the presence of God in social life.’* 1 Miiller, 5. S. 124. 2 Speech at the Berlin Religious Congress. SOME CONCLUSIONS 249 There is need also of more serious and systematic attempts to relate the thought of Christianity to the thought of India. Prof. J. S. Mackenzie says, in the pages of a Western journal, Tor us here at the present time there is probably nothing more impor¬ tant than the attempt to bring together the light that has been gathered by Western science and that which has been set forth by the saints and sages of the East 5 , and he adds pointedly, ‘perhaps it is chiefly in our religious and moral outlook that mutual understanding and toleration is important’. 1 Christian theologians have spent much labour in relating their doctrines to the thought of Greece, but they have hardly made as yet sufficient efforts to systematize their teaching or think out its principles in relation to the philosophy of India. Perhaps Prof. Heiler of Marburg lays too much stress on systematic elabora¬ tion, but nevertheless many will agree with him in his appeal for sustained intellectual effort: Tor the lasting conquest of the spiritual world of India/ he says, ‘the simple evangelical pro¬ clamation of the Word and life is not sufficient. For this there is need also of a theological labour on a gigantic scale, which shall link the fullness of the Christian revelation with the religious and philosophical possessions of India. ... There is need of a new Summa Theologica. . . . And this theological synthesis is in relation to India more difficult and more important than it was in the West (in the days of Aquinas) just for the reason that the religious and philosophical treasures of India are far older and richer than those of Greece. Without a theological work of this kind Christianity will never succeed in becoming to the Indian world what once it was to the Greek and Roman world.’ 3 And in similar fashion, but naturally with more intensity of emphasis, an Indian theologian writes: ‘Jesus Christ came not to destroy but to fulfil, and God who at sundry times and in * divers places spake to His children in India, does not desire that His word to our fathers should be made of none effect. In the same manner as the ancient philosophy of the Greeks was con¬ secrated to Christ, will the Indian Church make an effort to present her thought to the world, sanctified and made complete by the power of the living Christ.’3 1 Hibbert Journal, art. ‘International Unity’, Oct. 1926. a Heiler, Sadhu Sunder Singh, 228. 3 Coomaraswamy, International Review of Missions, art. ‘The Indian Church’. 250 RELIGIOUS VALUE OF THE VEDANTA It is our belief that the living Christ will sanctify and make^ complete the religious thought of India. For centuries—more centuries of civilization and culture than have been granted, perhaps, to any other nation—her saints have been longing for Him, and her thinkers, and not least the thinkers of the Vedanta, have been thinking His thoughts. Often they have not known His name, but they have been deeply conscious of His spirit, and their age-long thirst for communion with the living God and for realization of the nearness of His Presence will one day be satisfied. Then will the words of Jesus Christ become true also of India and her people: ‘Whosoever drinketh of the water that I shall give him shall never thirst; but the water that I shall give him shall be in him a well of water springing up unto everlasting life/ 1 f A* 'tL x /'\5 ohn iv - I 4- INDEX Abnormality, 225, 229 f. Absolute, 34, 45, 59, 62, 113, 128, 145, 153, 176, 182, 194, 201, 202, 205, 210, 211, 217, 224, 239, 240, 244* Absorption, 120, 179, 213, 226, 239. Abstraction, 1x6, 200, 202, 223, 226. Academic aloofness, 402. Acharya, 60, 61. Acosmism, 193, 213. Activity, Depreciation of, 182. Activity of God, 216. Activity of Knowledge, 122, 174. Activity of Self, 109, no, 122, 241. ‘Adequate Ideas*, 192. Advaita, 55, 58, 63, 98. Agni, 12, 14. Agnosticism, 135, 143, 230. aham Brahma asmi, 31 . Aitareya U., 23. Aiyar, Mr. C. N. Krishnaswami, 52, 64. ajhdna , 138, 141. akasa , 48. aldtasanti, 48. Alavandar, 61. alayavijhdna , 96. Alexander, Prof., no, 155. All-gods, 14, Alloy, 34. Alvars, 61, Andnda , 112, 157. Angus, Prof., 228. annamaya , 33. Anti-intellectualism, 228, Antinomianism, 125, 174. apard vidyd , 30, 113. Apostolical succession, 37. apurva, 162, 164, Aranyakas, 5, 8, n. Archer, 176, 182, 189. A-nstotle, 78, 2x6, 229. Arlen, Michael, 185. Arulnandi, St., 100, 142. Arundhati, 100. a$at, 57, 131, *49, 201. Asceticism, 23, 125, 174, 186. Asmarathya, 43. A4vagho§a, 94. Atharvaveda, 6, 19, 20, 131. Atman, 17-27, 31,. -132, 141, 193. Atonement, 188. Attributes, 194. Audulomi, 43, 168. Augustine, n, 246. Authority, 27, 37, 50, 66, 75 f., 227, 238. dvarana , 129, 140. avidya, 30, 36, 128 f., 201. avidya, as cosmical principle, 30, 48, 57, 138 f., 198. Badarayana, 42, 71, 72. Barnett, 36, 131, 138, 170. Being, i, 17, 34, 57, m, 131, 184, 198, 201, 204, 224, Being and non-Being, x, 18. Benares, 54, 55. Bergson, 226. bhakti , 61, 62. Bhagavatas, 44. Bhdgavata Parana , 62. Bhandarkar, Sir R. G., 72, 132. Bhashya, 51. Bhattacharya, M. L., 145. Blasphemy, 177. Bliss, 33-4, 157. Bloomfield, 20. Boehmen, Jacob, 106. Bosanquet, 172, 210 f. Bose, R. C., 174, 2x5. Bradley, 108, 210 f., 225, 228, 240, 242. Brahmacarin, 20. Brahman, 16, 27, 31, 33, 34, 57, 63, 68, in, 120, 129, 142, 147, 155, 193- Brahman, higher and lower, 67, 69 f., 86, 129, 149 f., 169, 196, 212. Brahman, with qualities, 43, 58, 62, 145, 163. Brahman, without qualities, 43, 45, 57, 113, 134, 143, 172, 192- Brahmanas, 5, 6, ii, 21. Brahmans, 37, 216. Brahma-sutraSy 39 f. Breath, 16. Brevity, 39. Brihaddranyaka U., 23, 27, 34, 36, 38, 69, 86, 115, 125. Brock, Clutton, 229, 240. Brown, T. E., 221, 238. Browning, 235, Buddhism, 5-46, 53, 54, 58, 60, 70, 92 f., 101,119, 135, 137, 183* 252 INDEX Caird, 189, 203. Canon, 45. Carpenter, Dr. J. Estlin, 5, 41, 78, 102, 142, 143. Categories, 56, 103, 108, 136, 197, 204. Categories, Use of lower, 226. Causality, 56. Chhdndogya U. } 23, 25, 26, 31, 32, 37, 80, 102. Childlikeness, 115. Christian Dogmatics, 41. Christianity, 246. city 112. Class-distinctions, 37, 60. Colebrooke, 73, 131. Coleridge, 121. Commentaries, 21, 40, 50. Communion, 169, 236 f., 247. Concentration, 75. Conditions, external, 36 f., 73 f. Conditions, internal, 38, 73 f. Conditions, moral, 38. Conditions, religious, 43. Conjeeveram, 61. Consciousness, Centrality of, 90. Conservatism, 4. Contemplation, 3, 38, 100, 123. Continuity, 92. Coomaraswamy, Dr., 249. Cosmopolitanism, xi. Cousin, xii. Cowell, 131. Creation and Cosmogony, 47, 62. Creation of Creators, 204. Creator, 57, 230. Cumont, 15. Cyclic Change, 184. Darkness, 38, 49, 68, 91, 125, 225, Das Gupta, Prof. S. N., xii, xiii, 3, 7, 10, 17, 22, 42, 44, 45, 47, 65, 72, 93 , 94 . 133, 138, 144, I 52 > 184. Das Licht vom Osten } 71, 220. Deception, 130. Deification, 81. Deism, 221. Deliverance, 3, 75, 113, 172, 184. Denotation of Words, 83. Despotism, 25. Destroyer, 58. Deussen, 3, 31, 38, 39, 41, 42, 50, 72, 82, 85, 88, 89, 115, 116, 125, 126, 128, 131, 135, 140, 149, 156, 161, 173, 178, 218, Devaydna, 58, 163, 168 f. Development, 204. Dewick, Rev. E. C., xiv. dharma , 81, 164. Discontent, 191, 220. Discursive Understanding, 198. Divine Companion, 236. Dogmatism, 75, 89. Dreaming State, 33, 48, 98, 117, 197, 213. Dreamless Sleep, 32 n., 161, 197. Dualism, 43, 44, 60, 63, 72. Dunning, 233. Dvivedi, Prof., xii. Dyaus, 12. Ecstasy, 20. Egoity, 172, 220. ekagratd, 3. Election, 37. Element in Absolute, 210. Eleusinian Mysteries, 106. Emancipation, 68. Emerson, 1. Empirical Self, 123. Epistemology, 216. Error, 206. Esotericism, 50, 54, 67, 73, 80, 156. Ethical Predicates, 183. Ethical Struggle, 212. Ethics, 172 f., 207. Eucken, 189. Evangelism, 230. Evil, 184, 196, 207, 244. Exotericism, 54, 60, 99, 156. Expiation, 20. External World, Belief in, 100. Externality, 213, 221, 232. Faith, 125. Farquhar, Dr. J. N., xiv, 22, 42, 43, 44.83- Fathers, Way of the, 58. Fichte, 198 f. Figurative and Literal, 87. Finite and Infinite, 215. Fire, Sacrificial, 13. Frazer, 63, 139. Freedom, 165, 185, 195, 196, 205, 213, 231. Galloway, Principal, 183. Garbe, 71. Gardiner, 236. Gaudapada, 46 f., 53, 93. Gita, 7, 23, 42, 43 , 44 £, 7$, 127, 1 55 , 244. Good and Evil, 195, 214. Goreh, Nehemiah, 11, 118. Gough, 38, 71, 72, 115. Govinda, 53, 93. Grace, 38. Greek Mysteries, 152. INDEX 253 Greek Philosophy, i, 13. Gross Body, 160. Guru, 8, 53, 61, 81. Haldane, Prof,, 209. Hallucination, 142. Happel, 130, 138, 148, 189. Hauer, 20, 26, 31. Heat, 161. Hegel, 88, 201 f., 213, 216, 219. Heiler, Prof., 249. Henotheism, 14. Heretics, 95. Hibbert Journal, 79, 134. History, 190. Holy Spirit, 239. Hopkins, Prof., 11. Hume, 97. Hutton, Dr. J. A., 185, 232, 236. hyle, 15. Hypothesis, 118. Idea, The, 203. Idealism, 16, 56, 88 f., 101, 157, 215. Ideals, Evaporation of, 214. Identity, 28, 31, 33, 84, no, in, 153 , 158, 159 , 176, 177 , 178, i 93 , 196, 199, 201, 208, 209, 213, 215, 217, 219 f. Ignorance, 57, 101, 129 f. Illusion, 47, 48, 88, 99, 100, 130 f., 193, 198, 200, 206, 207, 235, Immanuel, 247. Immortality, 13, 156 f., 196. Incarnation, 244. Indian Church, 249. Indifference, 186, 195. Individual Soul, 63, 67, 68 f., 91, 156 f., 179 - Individuality, 55. Indo-European Thought, 6. Indra, 13, 32. Inexhaustible and Inaccessible, 120, * 53 * Inexplicable, The, 144, 148. Intellectual Love of God, 196. Intellectualism, 108, no, 191 f., 204, # 208, 210, 212, 213, 230. Intelligibility, 39. Intensity, 220. Inter-subjective Intercourse, 138. Intuition, 35, 77, 113, 223. Irreverence, 237. Isa U.y 23, 38, 68. ishtdpurta, 164. Isodore of Seville, 41. Isolation, 235. Isvara, 32, 57, 140, 149, 152, 154, 156, 168. Isvara Krishna, 46. Iverach, 191. Jacobi, n, 71. Jaimini, 42. Jesus Christ, xiii, 238, 249. Juana, 125. Jndnayoga , 177. John, St., 242, 250. Joy, 134- Juliana of Norwich, 106. Kaladi, 51. Kali, 54. kalpa, 150. Kant, 89, 135, 139, 144, 198, 209. Kapalikas, 54. Karikas, 46, 53. Karma, 16, 125, 160, 162, 164 f., 184, 196, 205. karma-asraya, 162. karma-marga, 54. Karma Mlmamsa, 42. Kasakritsna, 43. Kdthaka U. } 23, 25, 26, 36, 38, 76, 80. Kaushftaki U., 23, 32, 69, 145. Kedarnath, 55. Keith, Prof. Berriedale, 11, 15. Kena U., 23, 123. Kingdom of God, 123, 126, 188, 238. Kirtikar, 55, 98, 102, 108, 146, 175, 180, 188, 201, 203, 217, 223, 235. Knowledge, Two Orders of, 43, 62, 67, 112 f., 153, 169, 192, 204, 212. kosa, 33. Krishna, 44, 127. kriyamdna, 170. Kumarila Bhatta, 54, 60, 93, 99. Laird, Prof., 119. Lankdvatdra , 95. Lasitude, 220, 222, 225. Law, xs, I 9 S- Law, Fulfilment of, 125. Legalism, 186. Leibniz, 192, 196! Limiting Adjuncts, 58, 110, 128, 140, 160. Lodge, Sir Oliver, 188. Logical Judgement, 207. Logos , 83, 241. Lotze, 116, 143, 151, 166, 209, 241, ^ 43 - Love, 196, 237, 242. Macdonell, 38. Macintosh, 205, 208. Mackenzie, J. S., 249. INDEX McKenzie, J. } 81. Madhusudan, 245. Magic, 18, 48. Mahabhdrata , 5. Mahdnardyana £/., 23. Maitrdyana U., 23. manomaya , 33. manas , 161. Mandukya Kdrikd , 46. Mandukya U., xii, 23, 34, 47 * Marett, 83. Maruts, 13. Marvell, 97. Materialism, 56. Matter, 45, 149* , , Maya, 29, 43, 47 , 57 , 59 , 67, 7 ° W 91, 119, 127, 128 f., 194, 198, 201, 203, 243. Maya , Relation to avidya, 143* Means and Ends, 186. Medievalism, 41. Mercy, 244. Merejkowski, 148, 171. Merit, 122, x 74 * Mimamsd Sutras , 50, 83. Mnemonics, 40, 50. Momentariness, 92, 96. Monism, 36, 44, 45 , 46, 55 , 61, 64, 100, 102, 192, 213. Moral Substratum of Soul, 162. Muir, 77. Mukhya Prana, 161. Muller, Max, 1, xi, 14, 38, 42, 4 <>, 63, 65, 71, 103, 115, 133, 135 , 144 , 181, 222, 248. Mundaka U., 23, 86, 87, 105, 113, 216. Mutts, 55. Mysterium tremendum , 2, 16. Mystery, 31, 139, 444 * Mysticism, 106, 108, 120, 187, 221, 223, 238. Myths, 2. Nachicetas, 26. Names and Forms, 29, 98, 103, 129, 157 * Naturalism, 58, 213. Necessity, 195. Negative Tendency, 13, 18, 24, 28, 34. 35. 45. 49. 55, 68, 112, 148, 186, 189, 207, 219, 223, 238. neti, neti, 35, 112. New Testament, 41, 114, 190, 207. Newman, 3. Nirgunam Brahman, 69 f. Nominalists, 29. Non-difference, 160. Nothingness, 96, 112, 201. Object, The Divine, 239. Objective Qualities, 56. Objective Reference in Ethics, 178, 180, 187. Oldenberg, 15. Om, 4, 83. Oman, Principal, 240. Opinion, 131. Ordinary Experience, World of, 35, 48, 57, 92, 94 > ii 3 » I 35 » 149 , 224. Organs of Sense, 161. Other, The, 236. Otherness, 215. Otto, Dr. Rudolf, 2, 16, 59, 91, 198. Pal, Mr. D. N., 52, 64, 81, 117, 142. Pantheism, 4. Pantheism and the Value of Life , 44, 67, 69, 147, 189, 206. Para-Brahman, 58. paramdrthika, 67. paravidya , 30, 113, 169. parindmavdda , 72, 132. Parjanya, 13, 165. Parmenides, 1, 48. Passages, Order of, 69. Passivity, 4, 38. Paterson, Prof. W. P„ 83, 222, 225; 237, 238. Paul, St., 125, 173 - Penance, 17. Perfection, 172, 188, 2x1, 214. Personality, 158, 216, 231, 241. Personality, Depreciation of, 187, 205.. Pessimism, 24, 184. Peter the Lombard, 41. Phenomenal, 57, 96, 136. Philosophy and Religion, 4 > 5 * Philosophy, Modern, 191 f. Philosophical point of view, 114. Physical, Dominance of, 227. pitriyana , 58, 163. Plato, xi, 1, 2, 131. Play, 133* Plotinus, 223. Plurality, 55, 120, 145, 211, 222. Poe, E. A., 143. Polarization, 129. Poussin, 46, 93, Prajapati, 14, 32. prakdra , 63. pralaya , 62, 149. pranamaya , 33. pranas, 165, 171. prdrabdha , 170. Prasna U., 23, 56, 82. Prasthdnatraya , 39, 44, 45 * INDEX ■ 25S Prayer, 16. Priest, 28. Pringle-Pattison, Prof., 119, iso, 134, 155, 196, 202, 203, 205, 208, 209, 239. Progress, 181, 184, 214. Projection, 181. Puranas, 61. Purity and Purification, 38, 12s, 188, Purpose, 134. purusha, 16. Purushottama Misra, 118. purvapaksha, 87. Purvapaksha, Great , 90. Quietism, 127. Radhakrishnan, Prof. S., xiii, 21, 22, 35 , 36 , 57 , 72 , 78, 94 , n°, 143, 144, 155, 175, 177, 180, 183, 210, 245. rag, 10, 51. Ramanuja, 7, 41,43, 5 ° f*» 65, 84, 89, 120, 134, 141, 145 , 149 , ISO, 157 , 158, 168, 176, 187, 192, 196. Ranade, 19, 23. Rashdall, 175. Realism, 45, 60, 90, 101, 106, 157. Reality, 18, 84, 113, 140, 210, 226. Redemption, 190, 244. Religion and Philosophy, 216 f. Religious Aptitude of India, 248. Religious Consciousness, 56. Religious Relationship, 201, 215. Religious Test Misleading, 216, Religious Test Superfluous, 215. Religious Value of Vedanta, 215 f. Renan, 191, 241. Responsibility, 184. Revelation, 113. Reverence, 239. Reward, 188. JRigveda , 6-12 f., 19, 37, I 3°* Rishis, 82. Pita, 15, 164. Ritualism, 13, 28, 58, 122, 124. Rivers and sea metaphor, 36. * Rogers, Prof., 195, 235. Roman Catholic Church, 79. Rope and Snake, 142. Russell, Bertrand, 105, 121, 209, 210 . &abda , 202. Sacrifice, 15, 27, 28, 24$. Sagunam Brahman, 69 f., 149 f. Saint, 225, 226. Salvation, 125, 199. Samaveda, 6, 19. samchita , 170. samsara , 139, 166, 186. Sankara, passim. Sankara and Buddhism, 92 f. Sankara and James Ward, 109. Sankara, Idealistic Attitude, 88. Sankara, Life of, 51. Sankara Method, 85. Sankara Orthodoxy, 65. Sankara, Pre-eminence of, 7 f., 54 - Sankara, Summary of Teaching, 55 f- Sankara-bhashya , 65. Sankhya, 45. Sdhkhya Kdrikds , 46. sannyasl, 53, Santayana, 195. §ariraka Sutras, 39 f. Sarvastivadins, 95. sat, 57, i3L 149 , 201. Scepticism, 224, 225, 227. Schilling, 199. Scholastics, 37, 77. Scientific Point of View, 114- Secret Doctrine, 22, 37. Self, Reality of, 99, 193, 225. Sen, Mr. P. N., 7, 64, 129. ‘Sentences’, 41. ‘Service’ God, 113. Seth, 206. Shastri, Prof. B. K., 18, 63, 104, 119, 125, 179, S29, 231. Shastri, Prof. K., 151, 15s, * 74 , 183, 244. Shastri, Prof. P. D., 17, 49 , 7 *> r 3 °, 133, 140/ Sheaths, 33, 58. Siddhdnta Sutras , 87. Sin, 244. Sins of Ignorance, 12. Siva, 23, 54. smriti, 77. Social Ethics, 179* Social Service, 126, 188, 199, 207. Society, 124. Solovyof, 125, 137 , 179 , 181, 236, 240. Soma, 13. Space, 56, 101, 135, 221. Speculative Freedom, 85. , Speculative Interest, 26. Spinoza, 75, 180, 191 f., 213, 216. Spirituality, 36. &nbhdshya, 62. Sriharsha, 229. Sri-perumbudur, 60. Srfrangam, 60, 61. Sri-Vaishnava, 60. iruti, 77. 256 INDEX Stages, Four, 124. Subject and Object, 106, 111, 215, 232 f., 237, 242. Subjective Qualities, 34, 109, 233. Subjectivity, r6. Substance r 119. Subtle Body, 160. Sudras, 37, 60, 73. Suffering, 200, 208, 244. Superstition, 227. Supreme Person, 59. Surya, 13. Suso, 236. Sutra Form, 8. Svetdsvatara ZJ., 23, 29, 38, 44. Symbolism, 36, 117, 148. Tagore, Dr. Rabindranath, 134, 144, i 55 > 230. Taittirlya U., 22, 149. tapas, 17, 27. tat tvam asi, 31, 104, 169, 216, 221, 333 > 247 . \ . . Tattvabhushan, Pandit, $8, 84, 92, 97, J27. Teacher, Place^.,3-7, 47, 73, 80, 81. X emple, Bish.0^229, 2^4. Theism, 43. ' ' ‘ Theodicy, 184. Thibaut, 42, 43, 44, 65, 67, 71, 140, 147,160. Thompson, Frances, 185. Thompson, Prof. J. Arthur, 85, 115. Thought, Centrality of, 202. Tilak, 11. Time, 56, 101, 200, 221.. ’ Tradition, 4, 84, 228. Transcendence in Ethics and Re¬ ligion, 178, 180. Transmigration, 19, 24, iafe, 167 f. Trichinopoly, 60. Tulsidas, 241. turlya, 33. Uddna, 94. Ultimate, The, 101 f., 194, 200, 220. Unity, Concept of, 36. Unity, Conditions of Search, 36. Unity of Apperception, 209. Unity, Search after, 14, 36. Universal, 56. Unknowable, 35, Unmanz, 33. upddhis, 129, 139, 140, 160. Upanishads, xii, 5, 6, 7, 8, 11, 21, 34, 36, 65, 86, 116, 131, 177, 221. Upanishads, Meaning of Name, 22. Upanishads, Vedantic Ideas in, 21 f. y ^AF | 4 /*■ ' Urquhasrt, Margaret M., 81. Usas, 12, 'J3. Vaiseshikas, 95, 96. Vaishnava Sects, 60, 61, 63. Vaisvanara, 32. Vaitathya , 47. Values, 183, 189, 190, 237, 238. VSnaprastha, 6. Varuna, 12, 13. Vasu, Prof. A. C., 47. Vasudeva, 45. Vasvani, Prof., 248. Vata, 13. Vedanta, passim. Vedanta, Meaning of Name, 7. Vedanta, Unity of Development, Vedanta Sutras, 6, 7, 21, 39 f., 60, 62, 65, 85, 90, 95, 102, 1 131, 137, 139, 150. Vedanta Sutras, Date of, 42. Vedantist, Typical, 64. Vedas, 1, 5, 6, 11 f., 37, 46, 60. Vedas, Date of, 11. Vedas, Fundamental Ideas in, 11 vidyd, 62. vijndnamaya, 11, 33, Vijnanavdda, 97. viksepa, 129, 140. Virat, 32. viseshyam, 31. Visishtadvaita, 63. Vishnu, 13, 44, 45, 63. Vi^vakarman, 14. Vivartavada, 72, 132. Vivekananda, Swami, 143, 176. Void, 47, 48. Vraty|i, 20. Vym y 42 , # S 4 , 82. .. Vydvahdrika Existence, 57, 67. Waking Life, 97, 197. Ward, 108, 109 243. Wenley, 173. Wilde, Oscar, 224. Will, Cosmic, 200. Women, Place of, 37. Word, 83, 203. Wordsworth, 106, 186, 220, 221. Works, 38, 12i f., 169, 188. Worsley, 218. Wright, Prof., 231, 241. Yadavaprakasa, 61. Yajurveda, 6, 19. Yama, 13, 163. Yoga, 23, 222. Yogi, 20, 45. d>erfluidum, 15.